Rhetoric and music.

The connections between rhetoric and music have often been extremely close, notably in the Baroque period. The influence of the principles of rhetoric profoundly affected the basic elements of music. (See also Analysis, §II.)

Interrelationships between music and the spoken arts – artes dicendi (grammar, rhetoric, dialectic) – are at once obvious and unclear. Until fairly late in the history of Western civilization, music was predominantly vocal and thus bound to words. Composers have therefore generally been influenced to some degree by rhetorical doctrines governing the setting of texts to music, and even after the growth of independent instrumental music, rhetorical principles continued for some time to be used not only for vocal music but for instrumental works too. What still remains to be fully explained is how these critical interrelationships often controlled the craft of composition. These developments are unclear partly because modern musicians and scholars are untrained in the rhetorical disciplines, which since the beginning of the 19th century have largely disappeared from most educational and philosophical system. It was only in the early 20th century that music historians rediscovered the importance of rhetoric as the basis of aesthetic and theoretical concepts in earlier music. An entire discipline that had once been the common property of every educated man has had to be rediscovered and reconstructed during the intervening decades, and only now is it beginning to be understood how much Western art music has depended on rhetorical concepts.

I. Up to 1750

II. After 1750

BIBLIOGRAPHY

BLAKE WILSON (I, 1), GEORGE J. BUELOW (I, 2–4), PETER A. HOYT (II)

Rhetoric and music

I. Up to 1750

1. Middle Ages and Renaissance.

2. Baroque.

3. Musical figures.

4. Affects.

Rhetoric and music, §I: Up to 1750

1. Middle Ages and Renaissance.

All rhetorically related musical concepts originated in the extensive literature on oratory and rhetoric by ancient Greek and Roman writers, principally Aristotle, Cicero and Quintilian. Among the enduring and influential legacies of this tradition is a fivefold division of the art of verbal discourse into inventio (finding the argument), dispositio (ordering the argument), elocutio (style), memoria and pronuntiatio(delivery), with the aim of moving (movere), delighting (delectare) and instructing (docere). Quintilian’s requirements for the well-trained orator included ‘knowledge of the principles of music, which have power to excite or assuage the emotions of mankind’. The emphasis of ancient orators on the significant role of music in oratory supported a continuous tradition of musical-rhetorical relations throughout these early periods, but the manner in which music and rhetoric interacted varied according to a number of shifting conditions, among them the accessibility of the ancient rhetorical treatises, the nature of the material conveyed in those treatises, the prevailing goals and functions of music and rhetoric within a given culture, and the various arenas of theory, compositon, performance and notation where one looks for signs of this interaction.

Broadly speaking, medieval rhetoric tended to favour eloquence, which emphasized the technical and structural aspects of form (dispositio) and style (elocutio), whereas Renaissance rhetoric favoured persuasion, which emphasized the orator’s strategies of inventio and delivery in affective speech that moved others to action. The former regards the structure of the argument per se, and reflects both the technical orientation of the Hellenistic courtroom manuals studied during the Middle Ages (Pseudo-Cicero Rhetorica ad Herenium, Cicero’s early De inventione) and the deployment of rhetoric within the fields of grammer, logic and written discourse. The latter regards the affective content and meaning of speech in relation to an audience, and reflects the rediscovery of Quintilian’s complete Institutio oratoria (1416), Cicero’s mature De oratore (1422) and, eventually, Aristotle’s Rhetorica, which advance rhetoric as an oral discourse within an integrated social system based on respect for civic life.

Having lost its oratorical moorings in ancient civic culture, rhetoric exercised an influence during the Middle Ages at once pervasive and diffuse, and points of direct contact between rhetoric and music are consequently difficult to identify. A shared vocabulary of such terms as trope (van Deusen, 1985), colores, clausula, copula, diminutio and variatiomay testify less to a direct influence than to the fact that the topic of tropes and figurae (the rhetorical ornaments of style, or elocutio) were universal and elementary aspects of a medieval education. Similarly, one could argue convincingly, but not conclusively, that the rhetorical practice of argument based on authoritative exempla (auctoritas) is manifested in the musical quotation, allusion and paraphrase found in, for example, plainchant-based polyphony, certain Ars Subtilior works and 15th-century imitation masses (Reynolds, 1995). The well-defined rhetorical techniques of memorization (ars memorandi, Enders, 1990) and delivery (the performance of ‘pictorial scripts’ stored in the memory) are latent in the development of such mnemonic aids as early notation and the ‘Guidonian’ hand (Berger, 1981), were certainly fundamental to the activities of medieval performers, and probably hold clues to the process by which standard melodic, rhythmic and even harmonic figurae could be retained and variously ‘composed’ in the memory. And while medieval theorists dealing with chant repertory evince an ongoing concern with text-music relations such as text underlay, accentuation and syntactical alignment (Harrán, 1986), these were primarily grammatical concerns, and the obscure relationship between medieval grammar and rhetoric makes it difficult to identify a specifically rhetorical strategy in either the theory or the repertory of chant.

As rhetoric and poetry were conjoined in the novae poetriae of scholastic grammarians like Matthew of Vendôme, Geoffrey of Vinsauf and Johannes de Garlandia, rhetorical elements of style embedded in the poetic text were mirrored in the musical settings. The shared concern is a concept of stylistic elegance based not on semantic content and its expression, but on rhetorical figures of ‘sound’ (Stevens, 1992) such as repetition, alliteration, assonance, syllable count, rhyme, metrics and rhythmics. These constitute a kind of verbal music that could be reflected in analogous, though essentially different, gestures of the musical setting such as the alignment of cadence and rhyme, the coordination of tenor repetitions with significant words, and the alignment of matching vowels in polytextual works. It is within this musical-poetic tradition that Machaut was a rhétoriqueur, and the harmonious co-habitation of these two ‘musics’ as described by Machaut’s ‘pupil’ Eustache Deschamps in his Art de dictier (1392) may be found, for example, in the repertories of the medieval lai (Stevens, 1992), Notre Dame organa (Flotzinger, 1975), and the early motet (Pesce, 1986).

The city-states of late 14th- and early 15th-century Italy provided the context for the humanist rediscovery of the practice and texts of ancient civic oratory, but circumstances favourable to the union of humanist rhetoric and music arose only at the turn of the 16th century. To be sure, signs of this union already may be seen in the declamatory passages in late Trecento works, the varietas and affective projection of text in Ciconia’s O rosa bella, and the use of fermata-blocked chords on important words in the works of 15th-century composers like Du Fay. There are widespread instances of ‘text-painting’, musical figurae that project the semantic meaning of the text (Pesce, 1986; Elders, 1981; Reynolds, 1995), but these are all essentially isolated examples, and the written (if not the unwritten) musical culture of 15th-century Italy was shaped primarily by northern composers influenced by late medieval modes of discourse.

The first signs of a significant interaction between music and humanist rhetoric appear during the generation of Josquin, by which time the first published translations of Quintilian and Cicero had been disseminated, and the first humanist rhetoric treatises had begun to appear. With the abandonment of medieval pre-compositional structures, like the formes fixes in the secular chanson and cantus firmus techniques in the motet, composers were free to explore new text-music relationships within the more flexible medium of an entirely original and through-composed musical fabric. A work like Josquin’s motet Ave Maria, virgo serena approaches the later 16th-century ideal of musical oratory, with its word-generated rhythms and melodic phrases, the careful pacing and sequential unfolding of its ‘argument’ through textural varietas and the manipulation of cadential closure and elision, and its overall mood of affective supplication. A heightened sense of rhetorical decorum, the matching of proper style (verba) to content (res), also led to the breakdown of medieval categories of genre and style at this time; surely the unusual gravitas of his chanson text led Josquin to apply motet texture in his setting of Mille regretz. The same rhetorical subjects of decorum and varietas surface in contemporary theoretical works. Tinctoris’s eighth rule of counterpoint in his Liber de arte contrapuncti (1477) reflects both Cicero’s precept and the increasing modal variety to be found in the works of Josquin and his contemporaries: ‘Wherefore, according to the opinion of Tullius [Cicero], as variety in the art of speaking most delights the hearer, so also in music a diversity of harmonies vehemently provokes the souls of listeners into delight …’. When discussing decorum in singing in his Practica musice (1496), Gaffurius urged that a ‘composer of a song should take care that words are set in an appropriate way to music’, and that the mode should be selected to that end. Gaffurius also adopted Quintilian’s division of oratorical delivery (pronuntiatio) into matters of voxand gestus when he advised the singer to avoid bellowing or excessive vibrato, and to refrain from a gaping, distorted mouth and exaggerated movements of the head and hands. Josquin’s pivotal role with respect to word-note relationship was acknowledged in the next generation by northern theorists like Glarean, Coclico and Hermann Finck. In Finck’s view (Practica musica, 1556) Josquin was the composer who showed ‘the true way’ from the veteres to the recentiores, who were distinguished primarily according to their concern with a correct and affective setting of the words.

The decisive bond between music and rhetoric was forged in the decades after about 1525, and by 1560 the concepts and terminology of classical oratory had made strong inroads into the writings of music theorists on both sides of the Alps (Wilson, 1995). On the model of Melanchthon’s adoption of rhetorical doctrines for Protestant scriptural exegesis and instruction in the new Lateinschulen, German theorists wrote music tutors that increasingly aligned rhetorical principles with the craft of musical composition within the new category of musica poetica. Listenius (1537) was the first to introduce this to the traditional Boethian duality of musica theoretica and musica practica, and subsequent works by Heyden (1540), Glarean (1547), Coclico (1552) and Finck (1556) established strong ties between Josquin-style polyphony and Ciceronian precepts of variety and decorum. Heyden and Glarean both invoked the rhetorical power of metaphor as described by Aristotle and Quintilian when they referred to the power of appropriate musical figures (figurae, colores) to place subjects before the mind’s eye (ob oculos ponere), a conceit that was repeated by later northern writers like Quickelberg (1560) and Burmeister (1601) with respect to the music of Lassus, and which surely constituted the theoretical basis for Renaissance ‘text-painting’. In the singing manuals of Coclico and Finck, Quintilian’s division of eloquence into correct speech (recte loquendum) and elegant speech (bene loquendum) was reinterpreted as recte cantandum (observation of correct accentuation, pronunciation and text placement) and bene cantandum (florid singing, or cantus ornatus employing coloraturae). In Dressler’s Praecepta musicae poetica (1563), compositional structure adopted the formal division of an oration into exordium, medium and finis. A German tradition equating the expressive function of musical colores (ornaments) with rhetorical colores (tropes and figures) was extended in the writings of Burmeister, who developed a detailed list of musical-rhetorical figures (Musica autoschediastikē, 1601; Musica poetica, 1606; see Rivera, 1993) that both summarized the Renaissance tradition and laid the foundation of a German theoretical tradition of musical figures for the next two centuries.

Musical-rhetorical relations developed along more radical lines in Italy, where they unfolded in the more rarefied air of the humanist courts and academies, which sustained both a more probing view of the condition of ancient music and a subtle and sustained interaction between music and emerging theories of vernacular poetry. Of first importance was Venice during the second quarter of the 16th century, where Pietro Bembo linked Ciceronian precepts of decorum and varietas to Petrarchan poetics (see Mace, 1969), and composers and theorists in the circle of Willaert came under the direct influence of Bembo’s Ciceronianism (Feldman, 1995). The Venetian context of text-underlay rules outlined by Lanfranco (1533), del Lago (1540), Vicentino (1555), Zarlino (1558) and Stoquerus (c1570) reflects an essentially rhetorical concern with recte loquendum. The composer Rore and the theorists Zarlino and Vicentino stand out as leading exponents of the application of Bembist thought to music as first demonstrated in the Petrarchan madrigals of Willaert’s Musica nova. In his Istitutioni harmoniche (1558), Zarlino borrowed the Ciceronian vocabulary of sonus (euphony and smoothness of speech) and numerus (well-structured speech), and applied them to a Bembist concept of eloquence: stylistic purity and restraint (the avoidance of contrapuntal errors, excessive divisions, chromaticism as a destroyer of modal clarity, indiscreet use of vox and gestus, and harshness) were to temper varietas (such as diversity of melodic movement and consonances, and avoidance of undue repetition) in pursuit of an elevated style characterized by the beauty and gravitas found in Willaert’s music and Petrarch’s poetry. Zarlino’s rapprochement between Franco-Flemish polyphony and the expressive ideals of oratory was particularly influential north of the Alps, where he replaced Gaffurius as the leading theorist of stile antico counterpoint. Drawing on the ancient Greek concepts of modal ethos and the genera, Vicentino proposed in his L’antica musica ridotta alla moderna prattica, (1555) a more radical notion of decorum latent in the sharp contrasts within Petrarchan language. In Vicentino’s extended concept of varietas, the ‘diverse passions’ of vernacular poetry may require that purity and even beauty be sacrificed to modal mixture, chromaticism and ‘every bad step’ and ‘bad consonance’, and the relationship to ancient oratory is explicit: ‘Now [the orator] speaks loudly, now softly, and more slowly, and more rapidly, and with this he moves the listeners very much …. The same ought to be in music’. Vicentino here framed the ideological (and essentially rhetorical) basis of the seconda pratica much as Rore manifested it in his madrigals. Among the next generation of musical humanists, Girolamo Mei had participated, as a disciple of Piero Vettori, in the revival of Cicero’s works on oratory and rhetoric, and had ‘read thirty times if once’ the Rhetoricaof Aristotle. In a letter of 1560 to Vettori, Mei proposed an Aristotelian system of communicative arts (arti fattive) that brought together the mimetic media of music, rhetoric, poetry and the visual arts, a prophetic confluence that was most aptly realized in opera.

Rhetoric and music, §I: Up to 1750

2. Baroque.

Not until the Baroque period did rhetoric and oratory furnish so many of the essential rational concepts that lie at the heart of most compositional theory and practice. Beginning in the 17th century, analogies between rhetoric and music permeated every level of musical thought, whether involving definitions of styles, forms, expression and compositional methods, or various questions of performing practice. Baroque music in general aimed for a musical expression of words comparable to impassioned rhetoric or a musica pathetica. The union of music with rhetorical principles is one of the most distinctive characteristics of Baroque musical rationalism and gave shape to the progressive elements in the music theory and aesthetics of the period. Since the preponderantly rhetorical orientation of Baroque music evolved out of the Renaissance preoccupation with the impact of musical styles on the meaning and intelligibility of words (as for example in the theoretical discussions of the Florentine Camerata), nearly all the elements of music that can be considered typically Baroque, whether the music be Italian, German, French or English, are tied, either directly or indirectly, to rhetorical concepts. In 1739, in Der vollkommene Capellmeister, Mattheson laid out a fully organized, rational plan of musical composition borrowed from those sections of rhetorical theory concerned with finding and presenting arguments: inventio, dispositio, decoratio – called elaboratio or elocutio by other writers – and pronuntiatio (see §I, above). Dressler’s structure of exordium, medium and finis was only a simplified version of the more usual sixfold division of the dispositio, which in classical rhetoric as well as in Mattheson consisted of exordium, narratio (statement of facts), divisio or propositio (forecast of main points in a speaker’s favour), confirmatio (affirmative proof), confutatio (refutation or rebuttal) and peroratio or conclusio (conclusion).

While neither Mattheson nor any other Baroque theorist would have applied these rhetorical prescriptions rigidly to every musical composition, it is clear that such concepts not only aided composers to a varying degree but were self-evident to them as routine techniques in the compositional process. Nor was rhetorical structure limited to German music theory. Mersenne, for example, in his Harmonie universelle (1636–7) emphasized that musicians were orators who must compose melodies as if they were orations, including all of the sections, divisions and periods appropriate to an oration. Kircher, writing in Rome, gave the title ‘Musurgia rhetorica’ to one section of his highly influential encyclopedia of the theory and practice of music, Musurgia universalis (1650); in it he also emphasized the analogy between rhetoric and music in the common divisions of the creative process into inventio, dispositio and elocutio.

The vitality of such concepts is evident throughout the Baroque period and later. Just as an orator had first to invent an idea (inventio) before he could develop his oration, so the Baroque composer had to invent a musical idea that was a suitable basis for construction and development. Since each musical idea must express an inherent or sometimes an imposed affective element of the text to which it was joined, composers often required aids to stimulate their musical imagination. Not every poetic text possessed an affective idea suitable for musical invention, but again rhetoric provided the means to assist the ars inveniendi. In Der General-Bass in der Composition (1728), Heinichen extended the analogy with rhetoric to include the loci topici, the standard rhetorical devices available to help the orator uncover topics – that is, ideas – for a formal discourse. The loci topici are rationalized categories of topics from which suitable ideas for invention could be drawn. Quintilian described them as ‘sedes argumentorum’ – sources of argument. On the most elementary level they were symbolized by the well-known questions that he posed for any legal dispute: whether a thing is (an sit), what it is (quid sit) and of what kind it is (quale sit). Heinichen (see Buelow, 1966) employed the locus circumstantiarum, namely the use of a textual antecedent, concomitant or consequent – a preceding recitative, the first (A) section of an aria, and the second (B) section or a subsequent recitative – as sources of musical ideas for aria texts. In Der vollkommene Capellmeister Mattheson criticized Heinichen for limiting himself to only the loci of circumstance and urged the full employment of several other locicommonly used by rhetoricians, such as the locus descriptionis, locus notationis and locus causae materialis. It is not unimportant that both Heinichen and Mattheson were practical theorists with long and distinguished careers as composers, during which they wrote vocal music for the opera house as well as for the church.

Rhetoric and music, §I: Up to 1750

3. Musical figures.

The most complex and systematic transformation of rhetorical concepts into musical equivalents originates in the decoratio of rhetorical theory. In oratory every speaker relied on his command of the rules and techniques of the decoratio in order to embellish his ideas with rhetorical imagery and to infuse his speech with passionate language. The means to this end was the broad concept of figures of speech. As was shown above (see §2), as early as Renaissance music, both sacred and secular, there is ample evidence that composers employed various musical-rhetorical means to illustrate or emphasize words and ideas in the text. Indeed the whole musical literature of the madrigal unequivocally depends on this use of musical rhetoric. Some authors (e.g. Palisca) have connected the late 16th-century practice of musical rhetoric to the definition of a musical ‘mannerism’, suggesting that this particular approach to composing may well be the explanation of the obscure term ‘musica reservata’. Of all the late Renaissance composers, Lassus was undoubtedly the greatest musical orator, as was frequently recognized by his contemporaries, and in the first Baroque treatise attempting to codify musical-rhetorical practices, by Burmeister, one of his motets, In me transierunt, was analysed according to its rhetorical structure and its employment of musical figures (see Analysis, fig.1). For more than a century a number of German writers, following Burmeister, also borrowed rhetorical terminology for musical figures, with both Greek and Latin names, but they also invented new musical figures by analogy with rhetoric but unknown to it. In this basically German theory of musical figures there are thus numerous conflicts in terminology and definition among the various writers, and there is clearly no one systematic theory of musical Figures for Baroque and later music, notwithstanding frequent references to such a system by Schweitzer, Kretzschmar, Schering, Bukofzer and others. The most detailed catalogue of musical figures (in Bartel, 1997) lists the different forms, taken from definitions and descriptions of varying degrees of exactness in many 17th- and 18th-century treatises, among the most important of which are J. Burmeister: Musica autoschediastikē (Rostock, 1601), expanded as Musica poetica (Rostock, 1606); J. Lippius: Synopsis musicae nova(Strasbourg, 1612); J. Nucius: Musices practicae (Neisse, 1613); J. Thuringus: Opusculum bipartitum (Berlin, 1624); J.A. Herbst: Musica moderna prattica (Frankfurt, 2/1653) and Musica poetica (Nuremberg, 1643); A. Kircher: Musurgia universalis (Rome, 1650); C. Bernhard: Tractatus compositionis augmentatus (MS, c1657); J.G. Ahle: Musikalisches Frühlings-, Sommer-, Herbst-, und Winter-Gespräche (Mühlhausen, 1695–1701); T.B. Janovka: Clavis ad thesaurum magnae artis musicae (Prague, 1701); J.G. Walther: Praecepta der musicalischen Composition (MS, 1708) and Musicalisches Lexicon (Leipzig, 1732); M.J. Vogt: Conclave thesauri magnae artis musicae (Prague, 1719); J.A. Scheibe: Der critische Musikus (Leipzig, 2/1745); M. Spiess: Tractatus musicus compositorio-practicus (Augsburg, 1745); and J.N. Forkel: Allgemeine Geschichte der Musik (Leipzig, 1788–1801).

Attempts by writers such as Brandes, Unger and Schmitz to organize the multitude of musical figures into a few categories have not proved successful. The following list aims only to give the most frequently cited musical figures in an equally arbitrary but somewhat broader group of seven categories: (A) Figures of melodic repetition, (B) Figures based on fugal imitation, (C) Figures formed by dissonance structures, (D) Interval figures, (E) Hypotyposis figures, (F) Sound figures, (G) Figures formed by silence. No effort has been made to enumerate all of the many variant names under which some of these figures appear in the literature, and the indication of a theorist’s name following the figure gives only one of often several sources in which the term is defined and discussed (see Bartel, 1997, for a more complete list of figures and sources).

Many of the musical figures, especially those from the earlier sources such as Burmeister and Bernhard, originated in attempts to explain or justify irregular, if not incorrect, contrapuntal writing. Although proceeding contrary to the rules of counterpoint, such passages were found to be suitable for dramatizing affective expression of the texts. Another large group of figures, the Hypotyposis class, have often been called madrigalisms (see under no.38 above) because they occur so frequently in Italian madrigals of the 16th century and later; word-painting occurs in music as early as medieval plainchant and continues unabated in the music of today. Finally, it should be stressed that while German theorists were almost solely responsible for the terminology of musical figures, this is not to say that similar figurative guidelines were not followed by composers in other countries in the 17th and 18th centuries (see, for example, the detailed analysis in Massenkeil, 1952, of musical figures in the oratorios of Carissimi). What German theorists rationalized was a natural and common element in the craft of every composer. Whether or not composers of other countries made such precise terminological associations between rhetorical figures and musical equivalents cannot be established, but that such musical-rhetorical emphases exist in their music cannot be questioned.

Rhetoric and music, §I: Up to 1750

4. Affects.

As a result of its intricate interrelationships with rhetorical doctrines, Baroque music assumed as its primary aesthetic goal the achieving of stylistic unity based on emotional abstractions called the Affects. An affect (‘Affekt’ in German, from the Greek ‘pathos’ and the Latin ‘affectus’) consists of a rationalized emotional state or passion. After 1600 the representation of the Affects became the aesthetic necessity of most Baroque composers, whatever their nationality, and the fundamental basis of numerous treatises. During the Baroque period the composer was obliged, like the orator, to arouse in the listener idealized emotional states – sadness, hate, love, joy, anger, doubt and so on – and every aspect of musical composition reflected this affective purpose. While it was easier to appreciate it in music associated with a text, the aim in instrumental music was the same. It needs to be stressed, however, that to compose music with a stylistic and expressive unity based on an affect was a rational, objective concept, not a compositional practice equatable with 19th-century concerns for spontaneous emotional creativity and equally spontaneous emotional responses on the part of an audience. The Baroque composer planned the affective content of each work, or section or movement of a work, with all the devices of his craft, and he expected the response of his audience to be based on an equally rational insight into the meaning of his music. All the elements of music – scales, rhythm, harmonic structure, tonality, melodic range, forms, instrumental colour and so on – were interpreted affectively. The styles, forms and compositional techniques of Baroque music were therefore always the result of this concept of the Affects.

Since the 19th century, writings on Baroque music have often referred to a so-called theory of the Affects (or ‘Affektenlehre’ in its commoner German equivalent), though in fact no one comprehensive, organized theory of how the Affects were to be achieved in music was ever established in the Baroque period. It has been assumed incorrectly, especially by writers such as Pirro and Schweitzer and those influenced by them, that composers worked with stereotyped musical-rhetorical figures – analogous to Wagnerian leitmotifs – in order to create a predetermined form of tone-painting. Other writers, including Bukofzer, continued to believe that such a stereotyped set of musical figures was an essential aspect of a Baroque theory of Affects. More recent research has clearly shown that a concept of stereotyped musical figures with specific affective connotations never existed in the Baroque composer’s mind or in theoretical explanations. Musical-rhetorical figures were devices meant only to decorate and elaborate on a basic affective representation and to add dramatic musical stress to words and poetic concepts. They functioned in music just as figures of speech function in oratory – as part of the decoratio.

The concept of the Affects was at least partly shaped by the writings of 17th-century philosophers of such diverse national backgrounds as Descartes, Francis Bacon and Leibniz. In an ever-growing stream of natural-philosophical studies in the 17th century, Descartes’ Les passions de l’âme (1649) became perhaps the most decisive in its influence on the art of music. This resulted from the belief that he had discovered a rational, scientific explanation for the physiological nature of the passions and the objective nature of emotion. Nor was music unique, for a similar concern for the Affects dominated all the arts in the 17th century. The attempt to understand the passions lies deeply buried in the history of Western art long before Descartes, however. The connection with the ancient concept of the four temperaments or humours should not be overlooked, and the ancient Greeks wrote at great length about the control of human emotions. They believed that music possessed an ethical force, or ethos, that was bound together with the modes. The Renaissance witnessed a convergence of the Attic philosophy of Ethos, the theory of the temperaments and a developing theory of the Affects, for example in the numerous definitions of the modes according to their affective nature. In later treatises these ideas ultimately became theories of Affects associated with keys, the best known of which was Mattheson’s in his Neu-eröffnete Orchestre (1713).

The association of rhetoric with the concept of the Affects can be found almost continuously in the history of music from at least the end of the 15th century. It is explored in most of the major treatises on Baroque music (see Buelow, 1973–4, for a selective bibliography). By the turn of the 17th century, for example in Caccini’s preface to his Le nuove musiche (1601/2), the musical goal of the singer became the moving of the affects of the soul (‘di muovere l’affetto dell’animo’). The German theorist Michael Praetorius, in Syntagma musicum, iii (1618), warned that a singer must not simply sing but must perform in an artful and graceful manner so as to move the heart of the listener and to move the affects. An Italian theorist, Cesare Crivellati, in Discorsi musicali (1624), devoted a chapter to ‘Come con la musica si possa movere diversi affetti’ (chap.11), and the English writer Charles Butler, in The Principles of Musik (1636), gave the purpose of music as ‘the art of modulating notes in voice or instrument. De wie [which], having a great power over de affections of de minde, by its various Modes produces in de hearers various effects’. Among the many works contributing definitions of the Affects in the 17th century is Kircher’s Musurgia universalis, an encyclopedic work, full of valuable information, where a theory of intervals as related to the Affects was proposed for the first time (see Scharlau, 1969). Of equal value are the several treatises of Werckmeister, who attempted to combine the rationality of mathematics with the rhetorical concepts of the Affects, providing a definition of particular value to an understanding of German late Baroque music.

In 1706 the German writer Johann Neidhardt, in his work on the tuning of a monochord, Beste und leichteste Temperatur des Monochordi, asserted that ‘the goal of music is to make felt all the affects through the simple tones and the rhythms of the notes, like the best orator’, and this remained the aesthetic credo of writers on music for much of the 18th century. Perhaps the most succinct and effective statement regarding the role of the Affects in music was made by Mattheson (in Der vollkommene Capellmeister): ‘everything that occurs without praiseworthy affects [in music] can be considered nothing, does nothing and means nothing’.

Rhetoric and music

II. After 1750

During the Enlightenment, philosophy and science developed new ideals of expression that greatly reduced the role of formal eloquence in intellectual life. Descartes objected to the use ‘des feintes et des déguisements de la rhétorique’, and the statutes of the Royal Society of London (1663) specified that all scientific reports should avoid ‘prefaces, apologies, and rhetorical flourishes’. John Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690) distinguished between the linguistic style suitable for ‘pleasure and delight’ and that appropriate for ‘information and improvement’. In the following decades, conspicuous exhibitions of traditional eloquence became unacceptable in discursive situations demanding truthfulness, although this did not preclude an appreciation of virtuosic oratory as literature: in the mid-18th century Frederick the Great could both carry volumes of Cicero on his campaigns and, in his judicial reforms, abolish harangues and appeals to the emotions from concluding arguments in court. Mattheson, whose position in the English embassy in Hamburg permitted close contact with British culture, echoed Locke in distinguishing between the plain language required of the historian and the florid style permitted to the rhetorician (Grundlage einer Ehren-Pforte, 1740).

Rhetoric was further undermined in the early 18th century as aestheticians, emulating the accomplishments of scientists such as Newton, sought overarching principles that governed all the arts. Whereas the ars oratoria had traditionally been concerned primarily with spoken and persuasive discourse, it became associated increasingly with written (and even non-verbal) media as part of the broader domain of belles-lettres. Rhetoric, however, now assumed a somewhat peripheral position among the arts. In Les beaux-arts réduits à un même principe (1746), Charles Batteux placed it between the mechanical and the fine arts: unlike music, poetry, painting, sculpture and dance, which have pleasure as their object, rhetoric (along with architecture) both provided pleasure and served some pragmatic objective. Because its utilitarian component involved considerations outside the realm of art, oratory would later be further marginalized in the aesthetics of Kant and Hegel.

The re-evaluation of rhetoric permitted its principles to be employed selectively, which in turn made possible numerous new analogies. Mattheson could thus enlist rhetoric in his efforts to disassociate music from the mathematical tradition. His enormously influential writings, however, treat the precepts of oratory with considerable licence: whereas Dressler and Burmeister had only been willing to create three-part models of musical organization (using rhetorical concepts in dividing the work roughly into beginning, middle and end), Mattheson advanced a detailed comparison of the da capo aria to the six-part oration. This analogy required, among other liberties, that the opening ritornello appear as both the exordium and the peroratio, despite the very different functions these two components serve in traditional rhetorical theory. Mattheson justified this departure from the ars oratoria simply by referring to the repetition as a musical convention and by noting that several psalms are similar in design to the da capo aria.

Mattheson's writings represent an important new development in the relationship between music and rhetoric. Although the music theorists of previous centuries had often invoked rhetorical terms and concepts idiosyncratically (see Vickers, 1984), their borrowings typically suggest a desire to appropriate rhetoric's prestige. The discrepancies that arise frequently reflect the difficulties of comparing dissimilar activities, and the theorists were generally no more idiosyncratic than the complex and contradictory taxonomic systems of the rhetoricians themselves. Mattheson, on the other hand, clearly regarded musical conventions as taking precedence over the precepts of his putative models; rhetoric no longer exerted priority over music.

Terminology and concepts drawn from the ars oratoria remained common in discussions of music, but by the middle of the 18th century new and often highly critical attitudes towards formal eloquence complicated the use of rhetoric as a source of imagery. In his Saggio sopra l'opera in musica (1755), Francesco Algarotti asserted that the overture of an opera should prepare the following drama, relating to it in the way that an exordium relates to the ensuing oration. Traditional rhetorical theory, however, did not require the exordium to refer to the subject of a speech (this function was assigned to the narratio), and the ancient orators left numerous independent proemia, or introductions, that could be prefixed to speeches on any topic. Algarotti therefore found that some composers did treat the overture as an exordium, but in precisely the way that he wished to oppose. He also complained of composers who resemble orators using ‘big and pompous words’ to display ‘the loftiness of their subject and the lowness of their genius’. In drawing on the oration as a model for musical procedures, Algarotti was therefore obliged to reject aspects of the rhetorical tradition that did not conform to his aesthetics.

Similar complexities surround a passage in Le neveu de Rameau (c1760) in which Diderot stated that ‘the aria is the peroration of the scene’. The metaphor implies that the aria, like the concluding section of a speech, endeavours to touch the passions. Although this clearly suggests a parallel between music and rhetoric, it appears in a paragraph portraying the rhetorical heritage as entirely unsuited to musical composition in the nouveau style of Italian comic opera. Within a decade of the Querelle des Bouffons, the orations of Demosthenes, Quinault's polished phrases and the declamation of classically trained actors could no longer provide a basis for music accompanying the exclamations, interruptions, shouting, groaning, weeping and laughing found in opera buffa. Such outbursts were not regarded as devices employed for specific persuasive purposes (as they would have been classified by traditional rhetoricians) but as spontaneous expressions of a character's passions.

A concern with the passions thus remained central to the later 18th century (and writers could thus still find rhetorical terminology useful), but the affections were no longer considered universal emotional states subject to codification according to rational principles. Instead, the passions were held to be highly changeable and uniquely individual, and the conventionalized representations of the affects found in earlier works began to seem stereotyped and unnaturally static.

These attitudes allowed a rhetorical manner of composition to be construed as a fault, as in C.F. Cramer's criticism (1783) of the procedures of Hasse and Graun. Yet in his Treatise published one year later, William Jones was still able to complain that Haydn and Boccherini lacked the rhetorician's demeanour. References to rhetoric are thus often rather general and tend to accompany remarks concerning the composer's need to cultivate a refined sensibility by familiarity with other arts. In Der musikalische Dilettant (i, 1770), for example, J.F. Daube suggested that composers employ the ‘light and shade’ of painting and ‘consider carefully the rules of oratory’. Rhetoric's changed status encouraged its treatment in such unspecific terms, and H.C. Koch (Musikalisches Lexikon, 1802), noting the unsystematic nature of writings on the subject, concluded that the composer should exercise ‘a sensitive artistic feeling’ in dealing with these fragmentary observations.

The writings of J.N. Forkel offer the final 18th-century attempt to develop a rhetoric of music. Although this founder of modern musicology is often characterized as a conservative, even reactionary, figure, his thoughts on rhetoric incorporated a progressive view of human psychology based on recent English philosophy. Forkel regarded the affections not as remaining constant until acted on but as inherently mobile and subject to an infinite number of modifications. Accordingly, the discussion of figures in the first volume of his Allgemeine Geschichte der Musik (1788) emphasizes concepts relating to the connection of musical ideas. Figures used to illustrate a text – a principal subject of previous musical rhetorics – are virtually ignored. Rather than being rationally quantifiable, as in Baroque music, affects are now considered entirely subjective and highly personal. Each piece reflects the inner character of its composer, and consequently Forkel considered superfluous the formulaic loci topoi that once aided the invention of both orators and musicians. Despite the importance of rhetoric in his thought, Forkel clearly regarded music as a true universal language superseding speech, which is merely conventional and therefore arbitrary. This accords with the views of authors such as Schiller, who regarded the arts as having ‘an absolute immunity from human arbitrariness’. Forkel's faith in the pre-eminence of music became common in the Romantic period.

18th century aestheticians often cautioned composers to portray the passions, not individual words or the natural world (see Hosler, 1981 and Neubauer, 1986). As music achieved a more elevated status, depictions of birdcalls and battles, while popular with the public, began to be regarded as a debasement of the art. Critics objected strongly to certain ‘madrigalisms’ in Haydn's The Seasons (1801), and Beethoven was careful to explain the Pastoral Symphony as ‘more an expression of feeling than painting’. As this phrase indicates, illustrative passages were often considered in relation to painting rather than to rhetoric; indeed, despite the proliferation of verbal programmes and descriptive titles in the 19th century, the programmatic works of the Romantic period owe little to the ars oratoria (see Programme music). In 1843 Schumann ridiculed the notion that ‘a composer working with an idea sits down like a preacher on Saturday afternoon, schematizes his theme according to the usual three points, and works it out in the accepted way’. By the middle of the 19th century the conventions of pulpit oratory were almost the only models readily available for Schumann's satire.

The main focus of rhetoric during the 18th and 19th centuries was execution and delivery (the pronuntiatio of ancient theory), and by 1785 the majority of rhetorical textbooks concerned elocution. Rhetoricians retained their respectability in this restricted domain; Kant, for example, contrasted oratory, which persuades by exploiting human weaknesses and is ‘unworthy of any esteem’, with excellence of speech (Wohlredenheit), which belongs to the domain of art. The treatises of C.P.E. Bach, Quantz and Leopold Mozart encouraged performers to study the techniques of successful speakers, and concepts of ‘proper declamation’ continued to be invoked in debates on the execution of Beethoven's works (see Barth, 1992). As rhetoric became almost exclusively associated with matters of delivery and pronunciation, vocal coaches came to be accepted as instructors; in 1867 Peter Cornelius (Wagner's répétiteur and a composer and trained actor) was appointed teacher of music theory and rhetoric at the Königliche Musikschule in Munich.

Rhetoric reached its nadir as a scholarly discipline at the close of the 19th century: in 1872 Nietzsche's course on its history attracted only two students and in 1902 Benedetto Croce noted that ‘rhetoric in the modern sense is above all a theory of elocution’. In such an environment the early 20th-century investigations of the musico-rhetorical tradition by Kretzschmar, Hugo Goldschmidt and Schering were important rediscoveries. The immediate cultural background supported the tendency (seen particularly in Schering) to regard the musical surface as saturated with rhetorical symbols, much as Wagner's operas were permeated with leitmotifs. In the mid-20th century H.-H. Unger compiled an extensive catalogue of musical figures, which he used to label the rhetorical devices presumed ubiquitous in Baroque compositions. The opening gesture of Schütz's Saul, Saul, was verfolgst du mich?, for example, was found to contain 15 such figures. In the late 20th century Krones extended this tradition to the analysis of works by Haydn, Mozart, Beethoven and even later composers. His account of the first three bars of Wagner's prelude to Tristan und Isolde proposes the use of exclamatio (the rising minor 6th), passus duriusculus (the rising and falling chromatic lines), catachresis (the ‘Tristan chord’) and suspiratio (the rest at the end of the phrase). Here figures no longer ornament the language, as in traditional rhetorical theory, but comprise the very stuff of the language itself.

The extent to which rhetoric impinged upon past compositional thought, however, remains a subject of much debate. Ursula Kirkendale's claim that Bach's Musical Offering was arranged according to Quintilian's Institutio oratorica met resistance from Bach scholars (see Wolff, Dreyfus, Walker and Williams), while Ratner's assertion that composers of the late 18th century used characteristic musical figures (‘topics’) associated with various moods, scenes and musical styles has been influential. Allanbrook has used this approach fruitfully to account for the dance types in Mozart's operas, where texts provide a basis for interpretation. Although Ratner's terminology recalls the topoi of rhetoric, the organization of melodic allusions in Haydn and Mozart cannot be shown to derive from the procedures of oratory; indeed, the loci topoi were being marginalized by contemporary aestheticians such as J.G. Sulzer and Hugh Blair. Moreover, as Diderot indicated, the idiom derived from Italian comic opera stood in opposition to the traditions of classical rhetoric. It may prove that semiotics, rather than rhetoric, provides the proper framework for the perspectives of Krones and Ratner.

Many recent analytical applications of rhetorical concepts are based on the presumption that during their study of Latin composers of the past were thoroughly indoctrinated in formal eloquence. Research into Bach's education, however, shows that much of his training in rhetoric involved rote memorization. Only on rare occasions was Leopold Mozart grateful for his knowledge of Latin (letter of 5 November 1765), and in a letter of 5 February 1778 he advised his son to purchase a German translation of the psalms before attempting to set them in Latin. Much of Mozart's instruction was probably practical, concerned with proper pronunciation and issues of text-setting rather than delving into the precepts of oratory. Wolfgang himself disclaimed the ability to ‘arrange the parts of a speech’ effectively (letter of 9 November 1777), and was already an established musician before he began to study Latin in the late 1760s.

It is thus difficult to see classical rhetoric as part of a comprehensive Weltanschauung influencing the compositional choices of late 18th-century musicians. In fact, the ability of contemporaneous theorists to relate the six-part oration to both the da capo aria and sonata form (see Bonds, 1991) suggests that rhetoric did not provide models for composers; rather, writers on music seem to have adapted rhetorical concepts to conform – however tenuously – to musical practice. Despite this, the study of rhetoric remains invaluable to an understanding of certain terms, such as inventio and Anlage, and provides much insight into the creative process in general. Indeed, the trajectory of rhetoric in the 18th century reflects significant changes in the way creativity was conceptualized: instead of following rules and formulae (such as are set forth in rhetorical treatises), artists came to be seen as forming their style according to their own nature. Numerous developments, including the interest in the biographies of composers, and perhaps the foundations of musicology itself, may be related to the declining position of rhetoric in Enlightenment thought.

See also Expression, §I, and Philosophy of music, §II.

Rhetoric and music

BIBLIOGRAPHY

middle ages and renaissance

H. Brandes: Studien zur musikalischen Figurenlehre im 16. Jahrhundert (Berlin, 1935)

F. Feldmann: Untersuchungen zum Wort-Ton Verhältnis in den Gloria-Credo Sätzen von Dufay bis Josquin’, MD, viii (1954), 141–71

F. Feldmann: Divergierende Überlieferungen in Isaacs “Petrucci-Messen”, Beitrag zum Wort-Ton Verhältnis um 1500’, CHM, ii (1956–7), 203–25

F. Feldmann: Das “Opusculum bipartitum” des Joachim Thuringus (1625) besonders in seinen Beziehungen zu Joh. Nucius (1613)’, AMw, xv (1958), 123–42

C. MacClintock: Molinet, Music, and Medieval Rhetoric’, MD, xiii (1959), 109–121

M. Leuchtmann: Die musikalischen Wortausdeutungen in den Motetten des ‘Magnus Opus Musicum’ von Orlando di Lasso (Strasbourg and Baden-Baden, 1959)

F.A. Gallo: Pronunciatio: ricerche sulla storia di un termine retorico-musicale’, AcM, xxxv (1963), 38–46

D.T. Mace: Pietro Bembo and the Literary Origins of the Italian Madrigal’, MQ, lv (1969), 65–86

C. Palisca: Ut oratoria musica: the Rhetorical Basis of Musical Mannerism’, The Meaning of Mannerism, ed. F.W. Robinson and S.G. Nichols (Hanover, NH, 1972), 37–65

R. Flotzinger: Vorstufen den musikalischen-rhetorischen Tradition im Notre-Dame Repertoire?’, De ratione in musica: Festschrift Erich Schenk, ed. T. Antonicek, R. Flotzinger and O. Wessely (Kassel, 1975), 1–9

W. Pass: Jacob Vaets und Georg Prenners Vertonungen des “Salve regina” in Joanellus' Sammelwerk von 1568’, ibid., 29–49

K. Schnürl: Musikalische Figuren in den vierstimmigen “Harmoniae morales” des Jacobus Gallus’, ibid., 50–62

W. Kirkendale: Ciceronians versus Aristotelians on the Ricercar as Exordium from Bembo to Bach’, JAMS, xxxii (1979), 1–44

H.M. Brown: Words and Music: Willaert, the Chanson and the Madrigal about 1540’, Florence and Venice: Florence 1976 and 1977, ed. S. Bertelli, N. Rubinstein and C.H. Smith, ii (Florence, 1980), 217–66

F. Reckow: Rectitudo–Pulchritudo–enormitas: Spätmittelalterliche Erwägungen zum Verhältnis von materia und cantus’, Musik und Text in der Mehrstimmigkeit des 14. und 15. Jahrhunderts: Wolfenbüttel 1980, 1–36

C. Berger: The Hand and the Art of Memory’, MD, xxxv (1981), 87–120

W. Elders: Guillaume Dufay as Musical Orator’, TVNM, xxxi (1981), 1–15

J.A. Winn: Unsuspected Eloquence: a History of the Relations between Poetry and Music (New Haven, CT, 1981)

F. Reckow: Vitium oder color rhetoricus? Thesen zur Bedeutung der Modelldisciplinen grammatica, rhetorica und poetica für das Musikverständnis’, Forum musicologicum: Basler Studien zur Interpretation der alten Musik, iii (1982), 307–21

R. Jonsson and L. Treitler: Medieval Music and Language: a Reconsideration of the Relationship’, Music and Language, Studies in the History of Music, i (New York, 1983), 1–23

M.R. Maniates: Music and Rhetoric: Facets of Cultural History in the Renaissance and Baroque’, Israel Studies in Musicology, iii (1983), 44–69

W. Kirkendale: Circulatio-Tradition, Maria Lactans, and Josquin as Musical Orator’, AcM, lvi (1984), 69–92

B. Vickers: Figures of Rhetoric/Figures of Music?’, Rhetorica, ii (1984), 1–44

N. van Deusen: Origins of a Significant Medieval Genre: the Musical “Trope” up to the Twelfth Century’, Rhetorica, iii (1985), 245–67

D. Harrán: World-Tone Relations in Musical Thought from Antiquity to the Seventeenth Century (Stuttgart, 1986)

D. Pesce: The Significance of Text in Thirteenth-Century Latin Motets’, AcM, lviii (1986), 91–117

J. Stevens: Words and Music in the Middle Ages: Song, Narrative, Dance and Drama, 1050–1350 (Cambridge, 1986)

D. Harrán: Elegance as a Concept in Sixteenth-Century Music Criticism’, Renaissance Quarterly, xlii (1988), 413–38

R. Dittrich: Textebezüge in den Ballata-Vertonungen von Antonio Zachara da Teramo: drei Beispiele’, Mf, xliii (1990), 15–30

J. Enders: Visions with Voices: the Rhetoric of Memory and Music in Liturgical Drama’, Comparative Drama, xxiv (1990), 34–54

M. Gozzi, ed.: Struttura e rettorica nella musica profana del cinquecento (Rome, 1990)

B. Meier: Rhetorical Aspects of the Renaissance Modes’, JRMA, cxv (1990), 183–90

F. Reckow: Zwischen Ontologie und Rhetorik: die Idee des movere animos und der Übergang vom Spätmittelalter zur frühen Neuzeit in der Musikgeschichte’, Traditionswandel und Traditionsverhalten, ed. W. Haug and B. Wachinger (Tübingen, 1991), 145–78

J. Enders: Music, Delivery, and the Rhetoric of Memory in Guillaume de Machaut's Remède de Fortune’, Publications of the Modern Language Association of America, cvii (1992), 450–64

M. Fromson: A Conjunction of Music and Rhetoric: Structural Modelling in the Italian Counter-Reformation Motet’, JRMA, cxvii (1992), 208–46

J.-P. Ouvrard: Modality and text Expression in 16th-Century French Chansons: Remarks Concerning the “E” Mode’, Basler Jb für historische Musikpraxis, xvi (1992), 89–116

J. Stevens: Music, Number and Rhetoric in the Early Middle Ages’, Companion to Contemporary Musical Thought, ii, ed. J. Paynter and others (London, 1992), 885–910

B. Rivera: Joachim Burmeister: Musical Poetics (New Haven, CT, 1993)

M. Feldman: City Culture and the Madrigal at Venice (Berkeley, 1995)

J. Hammel: Kadenz und Rhetorik: Studien zu John Wards sechsstimmigen Madrigalen (Saarbrücken, 1995)

C. Reynolds: Papal Patronage and the Music of St. Peter's, 1380–1513 (Berkeley, 1995), 280–97

B. Wilson: Ut oratoria musica in the Writings of Renaissance Music Theorists’, Festa Musicologica: Essays in Honor of George J. Buelow, ed. T.J. Mathiesen and B.V. Rivera (Stuyvesant, NY, 1995), 341–68

baroque

B.F. Richter: Eine Abhandlung Johann Kuhnaus’, MMg, xxiv (1902), 147–52

A. Schering: Die Lehre von den musikalischen Figuren im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert’, KJb, xxi (1908), 106–14

M. Kretzschmar: Allgemeines und Besonderes zur Affektenlehre’, JbMP 1911, 63–77; JbMP 1912, 65–78

H. Goldschmidt: Die Musikästhetik des 18. Jahrhunderts (Zürich, 1915/R)

J.M. Müller-Blattau: Zum Verhältnis von Wort und Ton im 17. Jahrhundert’, Musikwissenschaftlicher Kongress: Basel 1924, 270–75

A. Schering: Geschichtliches zur “Ars inveniendi” in der Musik’, JbMP 1925, 25–34

A. Schering: Bach und das Symbol, insbesondere die Symbolik seines Kanons’, BJb 1925, 40–59; 1928, 119–37

G. Frotscher: Die Affektenlehre als geistige Grundlage der Themenbildung J.S. Bachs’, BJb 1926, 90–140

J.M. Müller-Blattau: Die Kompositionslehre Heinrich Schützens in der Fassung seines Schülers Christoph Bernhard (Leipzig, 1926, 2/1963)

F. Stege: Die deutsche Musikkritik des 18. Jahrhunderts unter dem Einfluss der Affektenlehre’, ZMw, x (1927–8), 23–30

W. Serauky: Die musikalische Nachahmungsästhetik im Zeitraum von 1700–1850 (Münster,1929)

K. Ziebler: Zur Aesthetik der Lehre von den musikalischen Figuren im 18. Jahrhundert’, ZMw, xv (1932–3), 289

H.-H. Unger: Die Beziehungen zwischen Musik und Rhetorik im 16.–18. Jahrhundert (Würzburg,1941/R)

W. Gurlitt: Musik und Rhetorik’, Helicon, v (1944), 67–86

A. Schmitz: Die Bildlichkeit in der wortgebundenen Musik J.S. Bachs (Mainz, 1950)

A. Schmitz: Die oratorische Kunst J.S. Bachs – Grundfragen und Grundlagen’, GfMKB: Lüneburg 1950, 33–49

G. Toussaint: Die Anwendung der musikalisch-rhetorischen Figuren in den Werken von Heinrich Schütz (diss., U. of Mainz, 1950)

G. Massenkeil: Die oratorische Kunst in den lateinischen Historien und Oratorien Giacomo Carissimis (diss., U. of Mainz, 1952)

H. Federhofer: Die Figurenlehre nach Christoph Bernhard und die Dissonanzbehandlung in Werken von Heinrich Schütz’, GfMKB: Bamberg 1953, 132–5

M. Ruhnke: Joachim Burmeister: ein Beitrag zur Musiklehre um 1600 (Kassel, 1955)

H.H. Eggebrecht: Zum Wort–Ton–Verhältnis in der ‘Musica poetica’ von J.A. Herbst’, GfMKB: Hamburg 1956, 77–80

F. Feldmann: Mattheson und die Rhetorik’, ibid., 99–103

G. Massenkeil: Zur Frage der Dissonanzbehandlung in der Musik des 17. Jahrhunderts’, Le ‘Baroque’ musical: Wégimont IV 1957, 151–76

M. Lenneberg: Johann Mattheson on Affect and Rhetoric in Music’, JMT, ii (1958), 47–84, 193–236

H.H. Eggebrecht: Zum Figur-Begriff der Musica poetica’, AMw, xvi (1959), 57–69

K. Darenberg: Studien zur englischen Musikaesthetik des 18. Jahrhunderts (Hamburg, 1960)

G.J. Buelow: The “Loci topici” and Affect in Late Baroque Music: Heinichen's Practical Demonstration’, MR, xxvii (1966), 161–76

R. Dammann: Der Musikbegriff im deutschen Barock (Cologne, 1967)

U. Scharlau: Athanasius Kircher (1601–1680) als Musikschriftsteller (Marburg, 1969)

W. Hilse, trans.: The Treatises of Christoph Bernhard’, Music Forum, iii (1973), 1–196

U. Meyer: Musikalisch-rhetorische Figuren in J.S. Bachs Magnificat’, Musik und Kirche, xliii (1973), 172–8

G.J. Buelow: Music, Rhetoric and the Concept of the Affections: a Selective Bibliography’, Notes, xxx (1973–4), 250–59

G.G. Butler: Fugue and Rhetoric’, JMT, xxi (1977), 49–109

A.D. Stoll: Figur und Affect (Tützing, 1977)

G.G. Butler: Music and Rhetoric in Early Seventeenth-Century English Sources’, MQ, lxvi (1980), 53–64

R. Schollum: Studie über tonsymbolische Figuren’, Festschrift Othmar Wessely zum 60. Geburtstag, ed. M. Angerer and others (Tützing, 1982), 485–94

W. Arlt: Zur Handhabung der “inventio” in der deustschen Musiklehre des frühen achtzehnten Jahrhunderts’, New Mattheson Studies, ed. G.J Buelow and H.J. Marx (Cambridge, 1983), 371–91

G.J. Buelow: Johann Matteson and the Invention of the Affektenlehre’, New Mattheson Studies, ed. G.J. Buelow and H.J. Marx (Cambridge, 1983), 393–407

R. Toft: Music a Sister to Poetry’: Rhetorical Artifice in the Passionate Ayres of John Dowland’, EMc, xii (1984), 190–96

R. Wells: The Ladder of Love: Verbal and Musical Rhetoric in the Elizabethan Lute-Song’, EMc, xii (1984), 173–89

D. Bartel: Handbuch der musikalischen Figurenlehre (Regensburg, 1985; Eng. trans., enlarged, 1997, as Musica Poetica: Musical-Rhetorical Figures in German Baroque Music)

A. Forchert: Musik und Rhetorik im Barock’, in Schütz-Jb 1985–6, 5–21

C. Dahlhaus: Seconda pratica und musikalische figurenlehre’, Claudio Monteverdi: Festschrift Reinhold Hammerstein, ed. L. Finscher (Laaber, 1986), 141–50

C. Dahlhaus: Zur Geschichtlichkeit der musikalischen Figurenlehre’, Festschrift Martin Ruhnke zum 65. Geburtstag (Neuhausen-Stuttgart, 1986), 83–93

A. Forchert: Bach und die Tradition der Rhetorik’, Alte Musik als ästhetische Gegenwart: Bach, Händel, Schütz: Stuttgart 1985, i, 169–78

G.S. Johnston: Funeral Music and Rhetoric in Seventeenth-Century Germany (diss., U. of British Columbia, 1987)

M. Ruhnke: Figur und Affekt in Buxtehudes Choralkantaten’, Dietrich Buxtehude und die europäische Musik seiner Zeit: Lübeck 1987, 84–100

L.L. Matthews: Johann Kuhnau's Hermeneutics: Rhetorical Theory and Musical Exegesis in his Works (diss., U. of Western Ontario, 1989)

D. Harrison: Rhetoric and Fugue: an Analytical Application’, Music Theory Spectrum, xii (1990), 1–42

F. Civra: Musica Poetica: introduzione alla retorica musicale (Turin, 1991)

D. Schulenberg: Musical Expression and Musical Rhetoric in the Keyboard Works of J.S. Bach’, Johann Sebastian: a Tercentenary Celebration, ed. S.L. Benstock (Westport, CT, 1992), 95–109

W. Kirkendale: On the Rhetorical Interpretation of the Ricercar and J.S. Bach's Musical Offering’, Studi Musicali, xxvi (1997), 331–76

after 1750

G. Gruber: Musikalische Rhetorik und barocke Bildlichkeit in Kompositionen des jungen Haydn’, Der junge Haydn: Graz 1970, 168–91

W.S. Howell: Eighteenth-Century British Logic and Rhetoric (Princeton, NJ, 1971)

P. France: Rhetoric and Truth in France: to Diderot (Oxford, 1972)

C. Dahlhaus: Der rhetorishe Formbegriff H. Chr. Kochs und die Theorie der Sonatenform’, AMw, xxxv (1978), 155–77

W. Kirkendale: Ciceronians vs. Aristotelians on the Ricercar as Exordium, from Bembo to Bach’, JAMS, xxxii (1979), 1–44

U. Kirkendale: The Source for Bach's Musical Offering: the Institutio oratoriaof Quintilian’, JAMS, xxxiii (1980), 88–141

L.G. Ratner: Classic Music: Expression, Form, and Style (New York, 1980)

B. Hosler: Changing Aesthetic views of Instrumental Music in Eighteenth-Century Germany (Ann Arbor, 1981)

W.J. Allanbrook: Rhythmic Gesture in Mozart: Le nozze di Figaro and Don Giovanni (Chicago, 1983)

W. Arlt: Zur Handhabung der “inventio” in der deutschen Musiklehre des frühen achtzehnten Jahrhunderts’, New Mattheson Studies, ed. G.J. Buelow and H.J. Marx (Cambridge, 1983), 371–91

P. Williams: The Snares and Delusions of Musical Rhetoric: some Examples from Recent Writings on J.S. Bach’, Alte Musik: Praxis und Reflexion, ed. P. Reidemeister and V. Gutmann (Winterthur, 1983), 230–40

J. Neubacher: “Idee” und “Ausführung”: zum Kompositionsprozess bei Joseph Haydn’, AMw, xli (1984), 187–207

D. Schulenberg: the Instrumental Music of Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach (Ann Arbor, 1984)

B. Vickers: Figures of Rhetoric/Figures of Music?’, Rhetorica, ii (1984), 1–44

D. Bartel: Handbuch der musikalischen Figurenlehre (Regensburg, 1985; Eng. trans., enlarged, 1997, as Musica Poetica: Musical-Rhetorical Figures in German Baroque Music)

A. Forchert: Bach und die Tradition der Rhetorik’, Alte Musik als ästhetische Gegenwart: Bach, Händel, Schütz: Stuttgart 1985, i, 169–78

J. Neubacher: Finis Coronat Opus: Untersuchungen zur Technik der Schlussgestaltung in der Instrumentalmusik Joseph Haydns, dargestellt am Beispiesl der Sterichguartette, mit einem Exkurs: Haydn und die rhetorische Tradition (Tutzing, 1986)

J. Neubauer: The Emancipation of Music from Language: Departure from Mimesis in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics (New Haven, CT, 1986)

H.A. Schafer: ‘A Wisely Ordered Phantasie’: Joseph Haydn's Creative Process from the Sketches and Drafts for Instrumental Music (diss., Brandeis U., 1987)

A. Street: The Rhetorico-Musical Structure of the “Goldberg” Variations: Bach's Clavier-Übung IV and the Institutio oratoria of Quintilian’, MAn, vi (1987), 89–131

H. Krones: Rhetorik und rhetorische Symbolik in der Musik um 1800: vom Weiterleben eines Prinzips’, Musiktheorie, iii (1988), 117–40

L. Hoffmann-Erbrecht: Vom Weiterleben der Figurenlehre in Liedschaffen Schuberts and Schumanns’, Augsburger Jb für Musikwissenschaft, vi (1989), 105–26

H. Krones: “Meine Sprache verstehet man durch die ganze Welt”: das “redende Prinzip” in Joseph Haydns Instrumentalmusik’, Wort und Ton im Europäischen Raum: Gedenkschrift für Robert Schollum, ed. H. Krones (Vienna, 1989), 79–108

V.K. Agawu: Playing with Signs: a Semiotic Interpretation of Classic Music (Princeton, NJ, 1991)

M.E. Bonds: Wordless Rhetoric: Musical Form and the Metaphor of the Oration (Cambridge, MA, 1991)

L.G. Ratner: Topical Content in Mozart's Keyboard Sonatas’, EMc, xix (1991), 615–19

C. Wolff: Bach: Essays on his Life and Music (Cambridge, MA, 1991)

G. Barth: The Pianist as Orator: Beethoven and the Transformation of Keyboard Style (Ithaca, NY, 1992)

A. Liebert: Die Bedeutung des Wertesystems der Rhetorik für das deutsche Musikdenken in 18. and 19. Jahrhundert (Frankfurt, 1993)

E. Sismann: Haydn and the Classical Variation (Cambridge, MA, 1993)

E. Sisman: Pathos and the Pathétique: Rhetorical Stance in Beethoven's C-Minor Sonata, Op. 13’, Beethoven Forum, iii (1994), 81–105

P.A. Hoyt: Review of M.E. Bonds: Wordless Rhetoric (Cambridge, MA, 1991), JMT, xxxviii (1994), 123–43

P. Walker: Rhetoric, the Ricerar, and J.S. Bach's Musical Offering’, Bach Studies, ii, ed. D.R. Melamed (Cambridge, 1995), 175–91

L.D. Dreyfus: Bach and the Patterns of Invention (Cambridge, MA, 1996)

T. Beghin: Haydn as Orator: a Rhetorical Analysis of his Keyboard Sonata in D major, Hob.XVI:42’, Joseph Haydn and his World, ed. E.R. Sisman (Princeton, NJ, 1997), 201–54

P.A. Hoyt: Haydn's New Incoherence’, Music Theory Spectrum, xix (1997), 264–84