In its simplest sense, the term ‘expression’ is applied to those elements of a musical performance that depend on personal response and that vary between different interpretations. In this sense a piano teacher may enjoin a pupil to ‘put in the expression’, i.e. to play a piece with a certain articulation, tempo and phrasing. It is not clear how this use of the term relates to the concept that occurs in music criticism (as when a piece of music is said to express some emotion, outlook or idea). What does it mean to say of a piece of music that it has expression, or that it expresses, or is expressive of a certain state of mind? The question is a philosophical one, and reflects the profound uncertainty in contemporary aesthetics over the most important concept bequeathed to it by the Romantic movement.
For expression marks, see Tempo and expression marks.
I. History of the concept of expression
II. The nature of musical expression
NANCY KOVALEFF BAKER (I, 1), MAX HALLE PADDISON (I, 2), ROGER SCRUTON (II)
Expression, §I: History of the concept of expression
The Aristotelian doctrine of art as imitation of nature was fundamental to both artistic creation and evaluation until the late 18th century. Although the objects of imitation and its exactitude varied with the artistic media and different periods, the mimetic view of art long maintained a position as aesthetic dogma. Its modification and subsequent rejection for an expressive theory of art were caused by changes in ideas concerning both the relationship of nature to art and the nature of art itself.
Elaborating on the mimetic theory, the doctrine of the Affections related music to rhetoric in both its means and its end (see Rhetoric and music, §1, 4, and Affects, theory of the). It was thought that music could imitate both animate and inanimate nature, the inflections of speech, and the emotions. This imitation was accomplished by rhetorical method, and its aim was to arouse the listener. Such ideas are found in the Réflexions critiques sur la poésie et sur la peinture (1719) of Jean Dubos (1670–1742). He regarded art as a means of arousing moderate passions in men through imitation and thereby keeping them from boredom. In music, this could be accomplished by either a literal imitation of nature, such as tone-painting, or a higher type reflecting man’s inner nature, his passions. For the latter ‘one must … know how to copy nature without seeing it’.
In Dubos’ theory, imitation was merely a means to an end; a few decades later, however, Charles Batteux (1713–80) declared it to be the very purpose of art. In his Les beaux-arts réduits à un même principe (1746), he asserted that the one principle common to the arts, and indeed their goal, was the imitation of nature. Relying heavily on Aristotle, Batteux advocated copying not mere reality but rather ‘la belle nature’, a composite of perfections which enabled one to see the ideal behind nature.
For the next few decades, Batteux’s system was virtually unchallenged as the basis for French aesthetics. In England, however, some dissenting voices were heard. Charles Avison in his Essay on Musical Expression (1752) saw the perfection of a composition as arising from melody, harmony and expression, which, when combined, had ‘the Power of exciting all the most agreeable Passions of the Soul’. Imitation was no longer seen as the goal of music. Indeed, in his essay On Poetry and Music, as they Affect the Mind (1776), James Beattie (1735–1803) declared that with no disrespect to Aristotle nor to music, he ‘would strike it off the list of imitative arts’. The pleasure derived from music resulted not from its resemblance to nature, but from its power to affect the listener. Thus ‘if we compare Imitation with Expression, the superiority of the latter will be evident’.
William Jones (1746–94) made the definitive distinction at the conclusion of his ‘Essay on the Arts, Commonly Called Imitative’ (1772) (The Works of Sir William Jones, viii, 1807): ‘it will appear, that the finest parts of poetry, musick, and painting, are expressive of the passions, and operate on our minds by sympathy; that the inferior parts of them are descriptive of natural objects, and affect us chiefly by substitution’. Expression of the passions was now the most worthwhile aspect of art, while imitation was but a lower, technical skill. While Dubos believed that music could imitate the passions – that is, create in sound something resembling them – Jones credited music only with being expressive of the passions. There was intimated here a new function for the artist: no longer did he merely select from reality, seen or unseen; he now put into his work an element of interpretation. It was but a short step from such ‘interpretation’ to romantic subjectivity.
In France, the imitative view of art persisted, but its deficiencies came to be acknowledged. In his essay ‘De l’expression en musique’ (Mercure de France, 1771; written 1759), Abbé André Morellet (1727–1819) outlined an aesthetic philosophy directly descended from that of Batteux. Yet there was a recognition of the limitations of imitation, at least with regard to music. While acknowledging weaknesses in the mimetic theory, Morellet could not bring himself to abandon it. His observations, however, served as the catalyst to just such a renunciation.
Michel de Chabanon treated the problem of imitation most thoroughly in his De la musique considérée en elle-même et dans ses rapports avec la parole, les langues, la poésie et le théâtre (1785). He believed it was a fallacy that the arts, born of nature, devoted all their powers to ‘retracing her immortal image’. He concluded that music ‘does not imitate, and does not attempt to imitate’. When music did seek to imitate, it was unconvincing even in ‘reproducing’ the sounds of nature, such as birdsong. Unlike the natural model, the imitation was bound by both the laws of its art and the limitations of its medium. Imitations of outer reality were unsatisfactory because sounds, which were directed to the ear, had to detour by way of the mind and its concepts. In addition, the musical devices used for imitation were so unspecific that they could be used for a variety of interpretations, all equally valid. It was the unavoidable deviation from reality that was central to Chabanon’s argument. Attempts at imitation of inner reality, the emotions, were according to Chabanon equally futile. In denying that music was a language of the emotions, he rejected an entire philosophy based on the alliance of music and rhetoric. He believed that music was neither a derivative nor an imitation of speech, but a language in itself, independent of all others.
Despite its independence of signification, however, music could affect the emotions. This phenomenon Chabanon explained by a very subtle and original theory of analogy:
The melody which we shall call tender perhaps does not really place us in the same condition of body and of spirit in which we would be in actually feeling tenderly for a woman, a father, or a friend. But between these two conditions, the one actual, the other musical … the analogy is such, that the mind agrees to take the one for the other.
In the philosophies of Dubos and Batteux, the artistic imitation of passion aroused in the listener diluted versions of the same emotion. Jones, who did not subscribe to the mimetic theory, believed that the arts affected us by means of sympathy. The listener’s reaction was here a ‘feeling with’ and would seem to imply an element of volition; this was response rather than mere reaction, and the emotion need not be weaker than the artistic stimulus. Nevertheless, as in the earlier theories, the feeling of the listener was the same as that portrayed by the music; in a sense, the imitative process was merely relocated in the psyche of the listener.
Chabanon’s explanation by analogy, however, broke with even this vestige of imitation. The sensations of sound created aesthetic feelings in the listener, and these he could compare to emotional feelings. But, first, they had no relationship in terms of cause and effect; second, they were different in nature, the one aesthetic, the other affective; and third, they were separate from each other. The relationship was that of an analogy and nothing more.
The aesthetic feeling was a sensation more vague and comprehensive than specific sentiments. This was, in a way, a theory of meta-feelings, for to each aesthetic sensation could be joined many different particular emotions. Illustrating this versatility of music, Chabanon cited the duo from Grétry’s opera Silvain (1770), in which the same melody served texts of widely differing character. Thus the aesthetic sensation, conveying a general idea, was a kind of synthesis that could represent emotional contraries. The content of music was no longer an imitative interpretation of reality, but transcended it and was itself capable of many different interpretations. With this view, the relationship between art and the world was, in a way, inverted; the realm of art was now infinite in its possibilities compared with the limited world of appearances which it formerly had endeavoured to imitate. Chabanon’s conception of music as independent of all signification and imitation was basic to much subsequent thought. Ideas such as his led to the idealistic view of music that developed in the 19th century.
The economist Adam Smith (1723–90) concerned himself not only with the wealth of nations but also with the problem of mimesis. In an essay entitled ‘Of the Nature of that Imitation which Takes Place in What are Called the Imitative Arts’ (Essays on Philosophical Subjects, 1795), he expressed ideas often strikingly parallel to those of Chabanon, although the theory of analogy was missing. He believed that ‘whatever we feel from instrumental Music is an original, and not a sympathetic feeling: it is our own gaiety, sedateness, or melancholy: not the reflected disposition of another person’.
See also Philosophy of music, §§II, III.
Expression, §I: History of the concept of expression
A fundamental change in the status of music in relation to the other arts occurred in the years around 1800, the emergence of a new concept of musical expression coinciding with the rise of autonomous instrumental music as a serious art form. Whereas as late as 1790 instrumental music was considered by Kant (Kritik der Urteilskraft) as a mere divertissement of no serious importance, it now came to be regarded as the most elevated of the arts, capable of expressing feelings and ideas beyond the limits of rational knowledge. Music's new status thus constituted a complete inversion of its lowly ranking among the arts during the Enlightenment period. What had previously been seen as a disadvantage – that music without words could not convey definite meanings – now came to be perceived as its greatest advantage over all other forms of art.
W.H. Wackenroder, in his Phantasien über die Kunst, für Freunde der Kunst (1799), played a key role in the shaping of this new sensibility, asserting in these highly romantic and fragmented texts that musical material itself is endowed with mysterious expressive potential, and that ‘between the individual, mathematical tonal relationships and the individual fibres of the human heart an inexplicable sympathy has revealed itself, through which the musical art has become a comprehensive and flexible mechanism for the portrayal of human emotions’. This enthusiasm for heightened emotional states, which used music as the vehicle for rapture, as an art expressive of infinite and insatiable longing and indefinable feelings leading to ecstatic mystical revelation, is seen in the writings of numerous artists, poets, composers and critics of the period, notably in Herder's Kalligone (1800), in E.T.A. Hoffmann's novels, stories and music criticism, in the music journalism of Weber, Berlioz and Schumann, and in the novels of Jean Paul. Music was elevated to an art-religion, and was seen as the ultimate language of the emotions.
Among the most notable German Idealist philosophers of the period who attempted to incorporate the concept of musical expression into a large systematic philosophy are f.w.j. Schelling, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and Arthur Schopenhauer. Hegel, in Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik (1835, from his lecture courses given between 1820 and 1826), regarded music as an aspect of the self-realization of Geist (‘spirit’, ‘mind’), and, because of its intimate relation to ‘inwardness’ (Innerlichkeit), as the expression of the whole range of emotions that surround the soul. But at the same time, Hegel favoured vocal music and, like Kant, remained sceptical about instrumental music, seeing a certain futility in its retreat into ‘sounding inwardness’. Schopenhauer, perhaps the most important and influential figure in the mid-19th century aesthetics of expression, took a very different position. In Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung (1818) he argued that music is the most direct representation or expression of the Will, and is the art form most immediately capable of conveying this revelatory power and of freeing us from the force of the Will. His influence, particularly through the second edition (1844) of Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, was decisive for Richard Wagner, and is found both in Wagner's music dramas (most notably Tristan und Isolde) and in many of his theoretical writings on music, in particular the essay Beethoven (1870). Wagner's writings of the period 1849–51 (i.e. before his discovery of Schopenhauer in 1854) are themselves important landmarks in the aesthetics of expression – for example, in their anchoring of music's expressivity and articulation to the physical and gestural dimension of the drama itself in ways that are distinctly positivistic in character. In the later writings, however, the influence of Schopenhauer clearly predominates, notably in Wagner's statement that ‘music does not present ideas taken from everyday phenomena, but is rather itself a comprehensive idea of the world, automatically including drama’. The position of Friedrich Nietzsche relates both to Schopenhauer and to Wagner. In Die Geburt der Tragödie aus dem Geiste der Musik (1872), Nietzsche argued that the ecstatic, ‘Dionysian’ aspect of music is held in balance by the ordering, structuring, reflective ‘Apollonian’ aspect, and that the expressive power of music, and thereby its value, emerges from the tension between these two extremes. The paradigm for this theory of expression was, of course, Wagner's music.
There is a sense in which the theories of expression of Schopenhauer and Wagner, and to an extent of Nietzsche, come full circle, so turning into a version of the theory of imitation. But what is being imitated or represented now is not the outer world of nature. Instead it is inner nature, the force of the Will itself which, through this transfiguring power of music, gives immediate access to the world of Ideas behind the world of appearance, in a distinctly Platonic sense, but also in the sense of a form of ‘cognition without concepts’. This extreme version of the theory of expression as mimesis of the inner world of feelings also tips over into what is sometimes mistakenly regarded as its opposite, formalism. Eduard Hanslick offered a critique of the theory of expression in music that itself led to a position in some ways reminiscent of that of Batteux in the 18th century, in that the form of the work ‘expresses’ nothing but itself. In Vom Musikalisch-Schönen (1854), Hanslick set out to refute the expression theory of music, arguing that music traces the dynamic motion of a feeling, and that this is not the same as expressing an indefinite emotion, for to represent an indefinite emotion is a contradiction in terms. The first problem of music, therefore, is to give form to such dynamic motion. Thus he concluded that music expresses neither definite nor indefinite emotions; if it expresses anything it is the shaping of the musical idea, in purely musical terms. Because this is a dynamic process, it appears also to evoke the dynamic character of the emotions.
The influence, direct and indirect, of Schopenhauer's and Hanslick's theories in the later 19th and early 20th centuries was profound. It is seen in cross-fertilizations across the arts at the end of the 19th century. Symbolism can be understood as an exteme refinement either of the expression aesthetic or of the formalist, autonomy aesthetic, but is probably closest to Hanslick's notion of music as the dynamic shaping of processes that are analogous to the shifting experience and elusive character of the emotions. Yet at the same time Symbolism in the literary and visual arts and its equivalent in music, Impressionism, owe much to Schopenhauer's influence, particularly as filtered through Wagner. Early 20th-century Expressionism can be seen as the expression aesthetic taken to its ultimate extreme. But here too there is a paradoxical interaction of apparent opposites. On the one hand, Expressionism is the end point of Schopenhauer's notion of music as the direct expression of the Will, by way of the powerful influence of the Freudian concept of the unconscious (itself influenced by Freud's reading of Schopenhauer). ‘Expression’ in Expressionism is no longer the stylized representation of the emotions, or even the idea of the expression of the individual composer's emotions; instead, it is regarded as the direct expression of the overwhelming power of the unconscious. On the other hand, Expressionism itself was the extreme expression of Innerlichkeit, the withdrawal into the self (albeit a self in the process of disintegration). This withdrawal also indicated a move towards extreme abstraction and non-representation, and to this extent the influence of Hanslick can still be sensed.
Following the explosive culmination of the expression aesthetic in the Expressionist movement, the 20th century was largely dominated by an anti-expression aesthetic, epitomized in Stravinsky's aggressive rejection of Wagner (Poétique musicale, 1942) and in the Darmstadt School composers' rejection of the Expressionist residues in the music of Schoenberg and the Second Viennese School. The notion that music is about the expression of emotions nevertheless retains a powerful hold on the music-loving public, and the concept continues to provide a focal point for musical and philosophical aesthetics. The writings of Meyer, Cooke and Adorno represent three very different ways in which the theory of expression continued to be addressed in the second half of the 20th century. Each of these theories is also a theory of musical meaning and of music's similarity to language.
In Emotion and Meaning in Music (1956) Meyer set out a psychological theory of expression based on the idea of degrees of tonal tension and release, proposing that expression is the result of ‘disturbances in the goal-oriented tendencies of a musical impulse’ within a world of stylistic and syntactical probability. Meyer's theory also addressed the relation of uncertainty, instability and incompleteness to notions of teleology, syntactical probability and the expectation or anticipation of completion, of gaps being filled. Thus, as well as offering a theory of expression, Meyer in effect also put forward a theory of form. Cooke, in The Language of Music (1959), made an appealing if somewhat naive argument that it is possible to construct a lexicon of the expressive gestures of music's vocabulary. He itemized the range of ‘elements of musical expression’ as a system of tonal tensions, emphasizing that these can be understood both melodically and harmonically. For example, the ascending pattern 5–1–(2)–3 with a major 3rd stresses ‘joy pure and simple by aiming at the major third’, whereas the same pattern with a minor 3rd ‘expresses pure tragedy by aiming at the minor third’. He argued that such musical gestures are valid for all time, outside any historical or social context, and claimed a natural correspondence between musical ‘figures’ and feeling. In a sense, therefore, Cooke's theory of musical expression is also a mimetic theory. Adorno, in contrast, firmly contextualized the concept of expression, and proposed that the inscrutable character of autonomous musical works is the result of the contradiction between the logicality and rationality of musical structures and the apparent irrationality of expression. Adorno's position clearly owes something to Hanslick as well as to Hegel. He argued in Ästhetische Theorie (1970) that the previously mimetic, gestural and magical aspects of art are retained residually in the material of the work of art, but are now integrated into the work's ‘law of form’ through the powerful historical tendency towards rationalization. These opposing aspects interact, and ‘expression’ is seen as the result of tension between them, as what Adorno called an ‘interference phenomenon’. In this way, Adorno brought together mimetic and formalist theories to construct a Modernist theory of expression.
See also Philosophy, §§III–V and Rhetoric and music, §II.
Expression, §I: History of the concept of expression
J.G. Sulzer, ed.: Allgemeine Theorie der Schönen Künste (Leipzig, 1771–4, enlarged 3/1786–7 by F. von Blankenburg, 4/1792–9/R)
M. Schenker: Charles Batteux und seine Nachahmungstheorie in Deutschland (Leipzig, 1909)
H. Goldschmidt: ‘Die konkret-idealistische Musikästhetik im 18 Jahrhundert’, Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, vi (1911), 468–71
H. Goldschmidt: Die Musikästhetik des 18. Jahrhunderts und ihre Beziehungen zu seinem Kunstschaffen (Zürich, 1915/R)
W. Serauky: Die musikalische Nachahmungsästhetik im Zeitraum von 1700 bis 1850 (Münster, 1929)
R. Schäfke: Geschichte der Musikästhetik in Umrissen (Berlin, 1934, 3/1982)
K.E. Gilbert and H. Kuhn: A History of Esthetics (New York, 1939, 2/1953/R)
M.H. Abrams: The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition (New York, 1953)
L.B. Meyer: Emotion and Meaning in Music (Chicago, 1956)
D. Cooke: The Language of Music (London, 1959/R)
C. Dahlhaus: Musikästhetik (Cologne, 1967, 4/1986; Eng. trans., 1982)
T.W. Adorno: Ästhetische Theorie (Frankfurt, 1970; Eng. trans., 1997)
A. Lessem: ‘Imitation and Expression: Opposing French and British Views in the 18th Century’, JAMS, xxvii (1974), 325–30
E. Fubini: L'estetica musicale dall'antichità al Settecento (Turin, 1976, 3/1987; Eng. trans., 1990)
E. Lippman, ed.: Musical Aesthetics: a Historical Reader (New York, 1986–90)
B. Bujic, ed.: Music in European Thought, 1851–1912 (Cambridge, 1988)
A. Bowie: Aesthetics and Subjectivity: from Kant to Nietzche (Manchester, 1990, 2/1993)
E. Lippman: A History of Western Musical Aesthetics (Lincoln, NE, 1992)
For further bibliography see Philosophy of music.
1. Understanding of the term ‘expression’.
2. The impossibility of rules.
4. Expression, understanding, emotion.
6. Language, reference, information theory.
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
In every age it has been accepted that there is some relation between music and the passions – a relation, say, of instruction (Plato), of imitation (Aristotle), of arousal (Descartes, Mersenne), of ‘fusion’ (Santayana) or simply of some mysterious ‘correspondence’ about which nothing further can be said (St Augustine). It was from a sense of the emotional power of music that the Greek philosophers debated its political significance, that the Council of Trent considered how to subdue its influence in the liturgy, and that Calvin warned against its appeal in his preface to the Geneva Psalter. Yet the relation between music and emotion has remained obscure, and even when, partly under the influence of Rousseau and Diderot, the term ‘expression’ began to be preferred as the proper name for this relation, philosophers remained baffled as to its detailed character.
‘Expression’ must be distinguished from ‘evocation’. To say that a piece of music expresses melancholy is not to say that it evokes (or arouses) melancholy. To describe a piece of music as expressive of melancholy is to give a reason for listening to it; to describe it as arousing or evoking melancholy is to give a reason for avoiding it. Some kinds of popular music, being musically blank, express nothing, but still arouse melancholy. Expression, where it exists, is integral to the aesthetic character of a piece of music, and must not be confused with any accidental relation to the listener. For similar reasons ‘expression’ must not be confused with ‘association’, despite the strong arguments for the confusion given by the 18th-century followers of John Locke (among them Alexander Malcolm, J.F. Lampe and Joseph Addison).
It may be said of a performance that a certain passage is played ‘with expression’. When it is said of a piece of music (say, of Schubert’s Erlkönig) that it has ‘expression’, it seems natural to ask: what does it express? There is thus a presumption that expression in music is transitive: to have expression is to express something (in this case a feeling of terror). The piano teacher (or the critic), however, seems to be talking of expression in some intransitive sense, that is, in a sense which forbids the performer’s question: ‘what am I expected to express?’. That there are these two senses of the term ‘expression’ is made clear by the example of a face: a face may bear an expression of anguish, grief etc., or simply the ‘particular expression’ visible in its features. Two faces with an expression of anger would, in the transitive sense, have the same expression, since they express the same thing; but in another sense they might have a quite different expression, and in this intransitive sense it is impossible to give rules of expression. It is impossible to say which physical features in a face are responsible for its expression. If any feature is responsible then all are.
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
This feature of expression – that similarities in expression do not follow physical similarities in any easily specifiable way – can also be observed as a feature of ‘expression’ in music. Consider ex.1, from the last movement of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony. Often one may hear the fourth and fifth quoted bars hummed or whistled as on the lower staff: a very small change, but one that destroys the expression of the melody – its character (for example, as an answer to the passionate voices that had preceded it) is lost in such a rendering. Conversely, there may be similarities in expression between passages radically different in their physical character as sound: compare, for example, the passage from the ‘Eroica’ Symphony (ex.2a) with that from Stravinsky’s Symphony in Three Movements (ex.2b).
One fact might seem to become apparent from such examples: that there are no definite rules of expression in music, no rules of the form ‘if the music has features A, B, C then it will be expressive’. For to be expressive is to have a certain character, and that character is not determined by any one physical feature of the music but rather by the totality of its features operating together. It is therefore difficult, perhaps impossible, to say, in advance of the particular case, which features can be altered with impunity and which are vital to the effect. Sometimes the opposite seems true. Consider, for example, the ‘Todesklage’ from Wagner’s Ring (ex.3a). This theme contains a tense, tragic and yet questioning expression. One might wish to attribute that expression to the accumulated suspensions, together with the final chord of the 7th which gives to the whole an air of incompleteness. And it might seem that in so diagnosing the effect one has made reference to rules: suspensions introduce tension, 7ths uncertainty, and so on. Remove the suspensions, as in ex.3b, and the tension goes. Alter the final cadence and we have (changing the rhythm slightly) the serene introduction to Mendelssohn’s ‘Scottish’ Symphony (ex.3c). Could one really have predicted that expressive transformation outside the context provided by Wagner’s melody? And could one have known, in advance of the particular case, that, in removing Wagner’s suspensions, one would arrive at an effect of serenity rather than insipidity, or that in adding suspensions to Mendelssohn’s theme one would arrive at an effect of tragic tension rather than, say, cluttered portentousness? Clearly not. By all the ‘rules’ of composition a descending scale, for example, ought not to wear any particular expression; it ought to be an emotional blank, as in the banal theme from Beethoven’s Trio in E op.1 no.1 (ex.4a). But consider the slow descent of an E minor scale (changing to A minor) in the third movement of Bruckner’s Eighth Symphony (ex.4b). Here, because of the context provided by the cello theme that precedes the passage, the effect is of sublime tranquillity. A detail that could never have acquired expression because of any rule gains it from its context.
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
Insistence on the distinction between transitive and intransitive notions of expression naturally risks the question: why use the term ‘expression’ if there is not something important in common between them? This raises one of the most plausible of the Romantic theories of art, that of the Idealist Hegel. For Hegel, art could only be expression, on account of its character as an embodiment of the human mind. Art derives aesthetic, and indeed moral, significance from its relation to the ‘Idea’, from the fact that it can be understood only as a characteristically human product, as something that gives embodiment to mental life and conceptions. In some such way, Hegel might have argued, the expression on a face is understood, and even if the face is not associated with any particular state of mind, one is still justified in describing it as having an expression. For it must be treated as a representation of mental possibilities: there is no other way of seeing it, and the idea of studying the geometry of a face and disregarding its character as a revelation of mental life is intrinsically absurd.
Such a view helps to explain how it is that, even when referring to an expression in the intransitive sense, one may still go on to describe that expression in mental terms without implying the existence of any particular state of mind. For example, a face might be said to have a sad or a puzzled expression without any implication that it expresses sadness or puzzlement. Similarly, even in the case of the critic’s or the teacher’s concept of expression – which is clearly intransitive in the sense we have been considering – one may go on to describe the expression, saying, for example, that a particular passage should be given a mysterious or a melancholy or a wistful air.
All that seems to suggest a close connection between the transitive and the intransitive notions of expression. And indeed it has been characteristic of the Idealist tradition in philosophy that it has attempted to run together the transitive and the intransitive concepts, claiming, for example, that even if art does express feeling, the feeling expressed can be defined only through the expression, so that feeling and expression are inseparable and, being inseparable, incapable of being joined by any contingent relation. If there were such a relation, then expression would be governed by rules, rules which state how to express feeling A, how to express feeling B and so on; and that, as we have seen, contradicts one of our deepest intuitions about the nature of art. The argument belongs to the Italian Idealist Benedetto Croce. It was borrowed by the English philosopher R.G. Collingwood in formulating his celebrated distinction between art and craft, according to which craft is a means to an end and must therefore be conducted according to the rules laid down by that end, whereas art is not a means but an end in itself, governed by no external purpose. But since art is also, for Collingwood, essentially expression, expression cannot be construed as the giving of form to separately identifiable feelings or ideas. The feeling must reside in the form itself and be obtainable exclusively in that form. If it were otherwise, art would be simply another kind of craft, the craft of giving expression to pre-existing and independently identifiable states of mind.
It was Wittgenstein who first pointed to the distinction between the transitive and intransitive senses of the term ‘expression’. Obscurely, however, an awareness of that distinction underlay much of the 19th-century dissatisfaction with Romantic aesthetics. For the Romantic theory – according to which music was an expression of something, of the Idea (Hegel), of the Will (Schopenhauer), of ‘intuitions’ (Croce) or of feelings (Collingwood) – seems to try to have it both ways, saying that there is indeed something expressed by music, something which would perhaps explain the value of music, and yet, at the same time, refusing to allow that this thing could be identified except in terms of the particular piece of music that embodies it. In other words, it seems to want artistic expression to be both transitive and intransitive at once. In doing so it comes close to self-contradiction. In reaction to the Romantic theory Edmund Gurney attempted to re-establish the view of musical expression as essentially intransitive, and indeed as equivalent to the critic’s or the teacher’s concept. He wrote (1880, p.313):
we often call music which stirs us more expressive than music which does not; and we call great music significant, or talk of its import, in contrast to poor music, which seems meaningless and insignificant; without being able, or dreaming we are able to connect these general terms with anything expressed or signified.
Gurney went on to emphasize the teacher’s concept of expression, arguing that one does not look for passion in music in order to know how it is to be played; an understanding of expression is constituted by a desire to play in this way or that way, and it is that which must be taught. Such a thought comes close to a view that may (with some hesitation) be attributed to Wittgenstein: the view that a theory of musical expression is primarily a theory of the understanding and appreciation of expressive music.
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
It seems wrong to imagine that one could give an account of meaning in language while saying nothing about understanding language. Similarly, to follow Wittgenstein, it would be wrong to give a theory of expression in music which was not a theory of understanding musical expression; and that requires a total theory of understanding music. There is an essential connection between grasping the expression of a passage and understanding the passage, and, in a performer, ‘understanding’ means ‘playing with understanding’. A consideration of what that involves entails, for example, considering what it would be to play the violin theme of Bach’s aria ‘Erbarme dich’ (ex.5) with understanding. A player who understands puts the right emphasis on the slide at the beginning of bar 1, lingers just slightly on the D, perhaps leaves a breath at the end of the second bar. Such a player does not necessarily possess knowledge of some emotion, intention or idea that the music is purporting to communicate. The player's knowledge is essentially a practical knowledge, not a species of theoretical insight. A grasp of expression is no more than part of the complex activity of understanding music, an activity that has as its aim not the insight into particular states of mind but rather the performance and enjoyment of music.
Such a view of musical expression accommodates readily the sense, which many people have, that there is never only one way of describing musical expression, that every piece is open to new interpretation, and that no critic can fix for all time the meaning or expressive value of a particular musical work. For there will be, on this theory, as many ‘expressions’ to a piece of music as there are ways of understanding it, and just as a present-day way of understanding the Bach example need in no way correspond to the way in which it was understood by his contemporaries, so also may the ‘expression’ that the music wears today differ from that which was familiar to listeners in early 18th-century Germany.
However, despite all the scepticism that has been heaped on Romantic aesthetics, the popular view remains essentially that of Rousseau and Diderot: music evokes emotion because it expresses emotion. Music is the middle term in an act of emotional communication, and it is by virtue of that role that music acquires its value. Nor is this view – which involves a commitment to a transitive theory of expression – the exclusive property of Romanticism. It was foreshadowed, for example, in the Musurgia of Athanasius Kircher (1650), and to a certain extent even earlier in the works of Zarlino and Galilei. Moreover, while the influence of French 18th-century thought is certainly apparent in Romantic music, it could hardly be said that any true break in the actual practice of composition was brought about by these theories. Whatever might provoke descriptions of Beethoven’s late quartets in terms of the expression of feeling must surely provoke similar descriptions of the music of Josquin, Victoria or Dowland. And there is ample evidence that in all ages composers themselves have wished to characterize their music in mental and emotional terms. This we can see, for example, in the titles given by Lully, Couperin and Rameau to their keyboard pieces, or in the letters of Mozart and Beethoven; even Bach is said to have admired Couperin for the ‘voluptuous melancholy’ of his themes. Of course, there have been exceptions. The most notable was that great devotee of the ‘classical’, Stravinsky, who regarded the treatment of music as expression as nothing short of a conspiracy to subvert true musical values by measuring music against a standard extrinsic to its aims and inspiration. But Stravinsky, eloquent as he was, did not succeed in establishing his view of the total autonomy of musical practice, and his severe ‘classicism’ sorts ill with the deeply expressionist tendency of 18th-century aesthetics, the aesthetics of that period when music, according to Stravinsky, existed in its purest and least adulterated form.
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
Can the popular view answer the challenge in §4? That is, can it be incorporated into an acceptable theory of musical understanding? If not, then it will lead to a concept of expression that plays no part in the appreciation or evaluation of music, a concept that is musically irrelevant.
In fact, musical criticism may provide an understanding of music and yet never mention expression. Consider, for example, the criticism of Tovey, the thematic analysis of Réti, or the structural analysis of Schenker and his school. Such criticism and analysis leads to understanding by drawing attention to musical relations, thematic similarities, or, in the case of Schenker, a ‘deep structure’ which allegedly generates the musical surface. It is true that structural criticism may also refer to the ‘mood’ of a piece; and it is also true that, since the work of Tovey and (more recently) Charles Rosen, critics will describe the structural axioms of Classical music in ‘dramatic’ terms. However, each of those ideas seems rooted in a firmly intransitive notion of musical significance. The ‘mood’ and the ‘drama’ are there, in the notes, and cannot be described in terms extraneous to the musical movement. Among the works of Romantic criticism, the most valuable passages are not those where the critic attempts to diagnose an emotional state but those where he reflects on musical structure. And surprisingly, not only in E.T.A. Hoffmann, but even in Wagner, emotional diagnosis is only a part, and often a very small part, of the critical description.
But the argument is inconclusive. There has been important musical criticism of a wholly expressionist nature: perhaps Kierkegaard’s long essay on Don Giovanni provides the most striking example. Moreover, it could be that the relative silence of critics on the subject of emotion merely reflects the truth of another Romantic dogma – that emotions are in any case difficult to describe in words, and are more properly the subject of manifestation than analysis.
There are further difficulties for the popular view. The first, though not serious, deserves mention on account of its frequent occurrence in the literature. To speak of music as expressing states of mind might seem to imply that those states of mind must be attributed to the composer, in which case the judgment becomes open to refutation from the facts of the composer’s life, facts that would normally be considered irrelevant to an understanding of the music. (Thus it would be wrong to describe the first movement of Mozart’s Symphony no.41 as an expression of joy when we come to learn how unhappy the composer was at the time of writing it.) Such an objection would be misguided. Dramatic poetry, for example, is bound to be expressive of emotion in some transitive sense, and yet it would be absurd to say that it expresses the emotions of the poet. We cannot think that Shakespeare shared the sentiments of Iago or Racine those of Phaedra. In dramatic poetry the words express the imagined feelings of an imaginary character, and the poet attempts to create for his audience both the feeling and the personality who suffers it. Why should the same not be true of music?
A more serious objection may be found among the many relevant points raised by Hanslick. This objection asks: what are the objects of the feelings expressed by music? Most forms of art said to express emotion are also representational: they describe, depict or refer to the world. It is indeed difficult to see how emotions can be expressed in the absence of representation. For every emotion requires an object: fear is fear of something, anger is anger about something, and so on. Any attempt to distinguish emotions one from another must be in terms of their characteristic objects and in terms of the thoughts that define those objects. It would seem to follow that an artistic medium which, like music, can neither represent objects nor convey specific thoughts about them is logically debarred from expressing emotion. Such was Hanslick’s argument, and it is marked, like the rest of his short but influential treatise, by a philosophical seriousness and competence that have few rivals in the field of musical aesthetics. It is the inability of music to describe and represent the world – its narrative incompetence, as it were – that has most of all given rise to misgivings over the concept of expression in music, misgivings seldom felt in the discussion of poetry or representational art. For, when the objection is made, that the feelings conveyed by music can never be put into words, and so no serious agreement can ever be reached as to their quality or nature, the point is really that, since nothing can be said about the objects of musical feeling, nothing can be said about the feeling itself. To say, as Mendelssohn did (letter of 5 October 1842), that musical emotion is indescribable because it is too precise for words, is not an answer to Hanslick’s objection. Precision of emotion is always and necessarily consequent upon precision of thought. In other words, a precise emotion requires a precise situation, and that in turn requires a precise representation. Moreover, the complementary view – espoused by Mahler when he asserted that the need to express himself in music, rather than in words, came only when indefinable emotions made themselves felt – risks once again a return to the intransitive notion of expression: how can one distinguish music’s having an indefinable ‘expression’ from its being mysteriously related to an indefinable thing?
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
It is perhaps an awareness of this last difficulty that has led musical theorists to seek for ways of construing music as a vehicle of discursive thought. The most popular suggestion has been to interpret music as a language. Among those to have attempted such an interpretation is Deryck Cooke, who drew up a kind of ‘lexicon’ for classical music, citing examples of correspondences, persisting over a prolonged period of musical history, between particular shapes of phrase and particular kinds of expression. In terms of this musical lexicon he offered interpretations of entire movements, interpretations which attribute a narrative development to the music and offer a continuous ‘meaning’ to the movement as a whole. Such a theory is open to serious objections. For example, it is not clear how one is supposed to discover that the descending minor triad signifies, as Cooke says, ‘a passive sorrow’. The examples given suggest that the connection be discovered through the study of vocal music, by understanding a common reference in the accompanying words. In that case, one may object, the rules of ‘meaning’ are derived extraneously, and not from any linguistic capacity of the music. It may be that the descending minor triad is appropriate to the setting of certain feelings; but does that relation of appropriateness have to be described in linguistic terms? After all, black is the appropriate colour to wear at a funeral, burgundy the appropriate thing to drink with roast duck, anger the appropriate response to an insult. Does every human practice, then, amount to a language? To accept that would be to remove from the idea of language everything that is distinctive of it. In particular, meanings can be assigned to the words of spoken language only because what is said can be interpreted in terms of the true and the false. But the concepts of truth and falsehood, even on Cooke’s view, are not properly attributed to music. Some such objection can be raised against philosophers (the most striking example among contemporaries being Nelson Goodman) who have attempted to describe the ‘language’ of art in terms of such concepts as reference or denotation. There are powerful arguments, derived from Frege, which tend to show that, if the connection between reference and truth is severed, then it is not reference in any genuine sense that is being discussed. William Crotch had some inkling of Frege’s insight when, writing in 1831, he complained that music could not be a language since, if it were so, it would have to be a language without substantives – a language, therefore, in which nothing could ever be said.
Perhaps, however, music could be interpreted in some such way, as a language just in the sense that English is a language, a system of signs which both refers to objects and describes them. It would still not follow that music – as commonly understood – is an expressive idiom. In other words, the objection of §4 remains. For until the kind of understanding proper to actual musical experience can be shown to be already and intrinsically an understanding of music as a language, it will not be clear how the possibility of a linguistic interpretation enables one to appreciate, as a part of musical experience, the expressive character of works of music. The listener could find the music beautiful, and understand its character as art, and yet not dream that it is also a code that could be given independent meaning. Nobody has yet shown that ordinary musical understanding is linguistic in form, and it is doubtful that it could be shown.
Some philosophers have attempted to develop notions of reference which allow for the possibility of ‘reference without description’, in other words which break the connection between reference and truth. One such is Susanne Langer, who attempted to generalize the ‘picture’ theory of meaning given by Wittgenstein in the Tractatus to cover the special kind of meaning characteristic of musical works. Music, for Langer, consists of ‘non-discursive’ or ‘presentational’ symbols; it stands in direct logical relation to human feelings while at the same time saying nothing about them. This theory has been criticized, not only because the ‘picture’ theory of meaning has been thought (by Wittgenstein himself among others) to be fundamentally mistaken, but also because it seems that no theory of meaning could admit, as Langer wishes to admit, the possibility of a medium in which reference occurs continually but description never. Furthermore, in common with many philosophers who have discussed these matters, Langer assumes a view of the emotions as private, introspectible states of mind, consisting essentially of ‘dynamic’ episodes of an internal nature, which seems inconsistent with the acceptance of the general belief that an emotion is a motive to act, based on a perception and understanding of the world. One’s emotions no more consist in internal tremors and fluctuations than do one’s beliefs, intentions or desires (on this point see, for example, Ryle).
The failure of the linguistic view of music might seem to spell the doom of the transitive theory of expression. But there is another transitive view which attempts to escape the consequences of the objection attributed above to Hanslick. This view asserts that music expresses thoughts and emotions, but that such thoughts and emotions are ‘purely musical’. In other words, it asserts that the emotions or thoughts expressed by music cannot be characterized independently. In listening to music, the tensions, resolutions and developments that are characteristic of music are experienced, and while music has an effect on the emotions it is an effect that is peculiar to it and of which it is the sole proper object. Such a view will of course be merely empty until some means are found of describing the musical ‘thought’. Those drawn to the view have therefore attempted to give general theories of musical tension, and of the significance of tension in music, so as to be able to describe the logic of musical development and its emotional significance. A notable example is Hindemith; but perhaps the most ambitious attempt in this area has been that of Leonard Meyer, who has sought to characterize the meaning of music in terms of ‘information theory’, that is, in terms of the general theory of the predictability of successive phenomena. A musical event has meaning, according to Meyer, because it points to and makes us expect another musical event. The more predictable a particular note, for example, then the higher its ‘redundancy’, and the lower the tension that it adds to the musical line. By the analysis of redundancy, Meyer hoped to describe the progress of musical emotion, relating emotion to the development of tension in the musical structure.
While such a theory has an ingenious aspect, it is hard to know what it proves. Meyer’s account of ‘emotion’, like his theory of ‘meaning’, depends on premises that many philosophers would wish to reject. The least that can be said is that Meyer does not make it clear why such terms as ‘expression’ and ‘emotion’ should be used in describing the movement of the musical line. It may be an interesting fact that, looked at in one way, the ‘redundancy’ of classical music tends to maintain a certain constant figure; but that does not reveal anything important about ways of understanding classical music.
Expression, §II: The nature of musical expression
A return to the intransitive concept of expression does not dispose of the philosophical difficulties. Consider again the example of a face. A face can be said to bear an expression, in the intransitive sense, only, surely, because it sometimes expresses (transitively) the states of mind of its owner. It is because the face is the sign of independent thoughts and feelings that it can be called an ‘expression’ at all. Can the same be said of music? The considerations discussed seem to imply that it cannot. But what, then, entitles one to describe music as having expression even in an intransitive sense? If it has no expression in any sense, it is difficult to explain the role of music in song, dance and drama, or to explain such remarks as that of Saint-Evremond, who asserted that Lully’s operas were successful because their composer ‘knows the Passions and enters further into the Heart of man’ than the writers of the librettos. What Saint-Evremond said is clearly true; and it is evident too that much can be learnt about the ‘passions’ and about the ‘heart of man’ from music, as from poetry, painting or prose. Until there is an adequate theory of musical understanding it will not be possible to show how that can be.
R. Descartes: Compendium musicae (Utrecht, 1650/R, 2/1656); Eng. trans., MSD, viii (1961, 4/1965)
J. Addison: ‘The Pleasures of the Imagination’, The Spectator (21 June–3 July 1712)
J.F. Lampe: The Art of Musick (London, 1740)
A. Malcolm: A Treatise of Musick (London, 1752/R)
J.-J. Rousseau: Dictionnaire de musique (Paris, 1768/R; Eng. trans., 1771, 2/1779/R)
J.-J. Rousseau: Essai sur l’origine des langues (Geneva, 1781)
D. Diderot: Le neveu de Rameau (Paris, 1821; Eng. trans., 1966)
G. Santayana: The Sense of Beauty (London and Norwood, MA, 1896)
B. Bosanquet: ‘On the Nature of Aesthetic Emotion’, Science and Philosophy (London, 1927)
J.-P. Sartre: L’imaginaire (Paris, 1940; Eng. trans., 1948/R), 53–63
L. Wittgenstein: Preliminary Studies for the ‘Philosophical Investigations’, Generally known as the Blue and Brown Books (Oxford, 1958, 2/1969), 170ff
W.D. Anderson: Ethos and Education in Greek Music (Cambridge, MA, 1966, 2/1968)
C. Barrett, ed.: L. Wittgenstein: Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, i (Oxford, 1966), 28–36
R. Wollheim: Art and its Objects (New York, 1968), 95–7
E. Gurney: The Power of Sound (London, 1880), 322ff
F.N. Sibley: ‘Aesthetic Concepts’, Philosophical Review, lxxviii (1959), 421–50
F.N. Sibley: ‘Aesthetic and Non-Aesthetic’, Philosophical Review, lxxxiv (1965), 135–59
I. Kant: Kritik der Urteilskraft (Berlin, 1790; Eng. trans., 1952)
W.H. Wackenroder: Herzensergiessungen eines kunstliebenden Klosterbruders (Berlin, 1797)
A. Schopenhauer: Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, ii (Leipzig, 1819; Eng. trans., 1958)
G.W.F. Hegel: Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik (Berlin, 1835, 2/1842; Eng. trans., 1975, as Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art)
E. Gurney: The Power of Sound (London, 1880)
B. Croce: Estetica come scienza dell’espressione e linguistica generale (Milan, 1902, 4/1912; Eng. trans., 1909, 2/1922/R)
R.G. Collingwood: The Principles of Art (Oxford, 1938)
G. Zarlino: Le istitutioni harmoniche (Venice, 1558/R, 3/1573/R; Eng. trans. of pt ii, 1968, as The Art of Counterpoint)
V. Galilei: Dialogo della musica antica et della moderna (Florence, 1581/R)
A. Kircher: Musurgia universalis (Rome, 1650/R)
C. Avison: An Essay on Musical Expression (London, 1752, 2/1753/R, 3/1775)
D. Diderot: Le neveu de Rameau (MS, c1760); ed. J. Fabre (Geneva, 1950, 2/1963; Eng. trans., 1965)
L. Klages: Ausdrucksbewegung und Gestaltungskraft (Leipzig, 1913)
J.W.N. Sullivan: Beethoven: his Spiritual Development (New York, 1927)
K. Bühler: Ausdruckstheorie (Jena, 1933)
L. Klages: Grundlegung der Wissenschaft vom Ausdruck (Leipzig, 1936)
A. Wellek: ‘Gefühl und Kunst’, Neue psychologische Studien, xiv (1939), 1–24
I. Stravinsky: Poétique musicale sous forme de six leçons (Cambridge, MA, 1942; Eng. trans., 1947); Eng. and Fr. edn (Cambridge, MA, 1970)
W. Mellers: François Couperin and the French Classical Tradition (London, 1950/R), 25
V. Zuckerkandl: Sound and Symbol: Music and the External World (London and New York, 1956; Ger. orig., 1963)
L. Wittgenstein: Zettel (Oxford, 1967; Ger. orig.), 28–31
R. Scruton: Art and Imagination (London, 1974), 168–87, 213–26
E.T.A. Hoffmann: Schriften zur Musik, Nachlese (Berlin, 1827); ed. F. Schnapp (Munich, 1963, 2/1978)
F. Mendelssohn: Letter to Marc André Souchay, Berlin, 5 Oct 1842
S. Kierkegaard: ‘De umiddelbare erotiske Stadier eller det Musikalsk-Erotiske’, Enten-eller: et Livs-Fragment, i (Copenhagen, 1843/R), 31–128 ; Eng. trans. (Princeton, NJ, 1944/R), i, 34–110
E. Hanslick: Vom Musikalisch-Schönen (Leipzig, 1854/R, 16/1966; Eng. trans., 1891/R); ed. and Eng. trans. G. Payzant (Indianapolis, IN, 1986)
W.A. Ellis, ed. and trans.: Richard Wagner’s Prose Works (London, 1892–9), esp. vol.iii
H. Kretzschmar: ‘Anregungen zur Förderung musikalischer Hermeneutik’, JbMP 1902, 45–66; JbMP 1905, 73–86
H. Schenker: Neue musikalische Theorien und Phantasien, i: Harmonielehre (Stuttgart, 1906; Eng. trans., 1954/R, ed. O. Jonas)
C.C. Pratt: The Meaning of Music: a Study in Psychological Aesthetics (New York, 1931/R)
D.F. Tovey: Essays in Musical Analysis (London, 1935–9/R, abridged 2/1981)
A. Mahler: Gustav Mahler: Erinnerungen und Briefe (Amsterdam, 1940; Eng. trans., 1946, rev., enlarged 3/1975 by D. Mitchell and K. Martner)
J. Hospers: Meaning and Truth in the Arts (Chapel Hill, NC, 1946)
R. Réti: The Thematic Process in Music (New York, 1951)
F. Salzer: Structural Hearing: Tonal Coherence in Music (New York, 1952, 2/1962)
W.K. Wimsatt and M.C. Beardsley: ‘The Intentional Fallacy’, in W.K. Wimsatt: The Verbal Icon (Lexington, KY, 1954), 3–18
A. Kenny: Action, Emotion and Will (London, 1963)
C. Rosen: The Classical Style: Haydn, Mozart, Beethoven (London and New York, 1971, 2/1972)
R. Scruton: ‘Representation in Music’, Philosophy, li (1976), 273–87
W. Crotch: Substance of Several Courses of Lectures on Music Read in the University of Oxford and the Metropolis (London, 1831)
L. Wittgenstein: Tractatus logico-philosophicus (London, 1922/R; Ger. orig.)
K. Huber: Der Ausdruck musikalischer Elementarmotive (Leipzig, 1923)
P. Hindemith: Unterweisung im Tonsatz, i: Theoretischer Teil (Mainz, 1937, 2/1940; Eng. trans., 1942, 2/1948)
S.K. Langer: Philosophy in a New Key (Cambridge, MA, 1942/R)
G. Ryle: The Concept of Mind (London, 1949/R)
G. Frege: ‘On Sense and Reference’, Translations from the Philosophical Writings, ed. P. Geach and M. Black (Oxford, 1952), 56–78
L. Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations (Oxford, 1953; Ger. orig.)
L.B. Meyer: Emotion and Meaning in Music (Chicago, 1956)
D. Cooke: The Language of Music (Oxford, 1959/R)
N. Goodman: Languages of Art (Indianapolis, IN, 1968)
R. Wollheim: Art and its Objects (New York, 1968, 2/1980), 114–17
V.A. Howard: ‘On Musical Expression’, British Journal of Aesthetics, iv (1971), 268–80
V.A. Howard: ‘On Representational Music’, Noûs, iv/1 (1972), 41–53
O.K. Bouwsma: ‘The Expression Theory of Art’, Philosophical Analysis, ed. M. Black (Ithaca, NY, 1950), 75–101
E.H. Gombrich: Art and Illusion (London and New York, 1960), 359–89
E.H. Gombrich: Meditations on a Hobby Horse (London and New York, 3/1968)
S. Cavell: Must We Mean What We Say? (New York, 1969/R) [esp. article ‘Music Discomposed’, 180–212]
L.A. Reid: Meaning in the Arts (London and New York, 1969), 93–185
W. Charlton: Aesthetics: an Introduction (London, 1970), 84–100
A. Tormey: The Concept of Expression (Princeton, NJ, 1971)
R. Wollheim: ‘Expression’, On Art and the Mind (London, 1973), 84–100
M. Budd: Music and the Emotions: the Philosophical Theories (London, 1985)
P. Kivy: Music Alone (Ithaca, NY, 1990)
J. Levinson: Music, Arts and Metaphysics (Ithaca, NY, 1990)
P. Kivy: Sound Sentiment (Philadelphia, 1991)
D. Raffman: Language, Music and Mind (Cambridge, MA, 1993)
S. Davies: Musical Meaning and Expression (Ithaca, NY, 1994)
M. Budd: Values of Art (London, 1995)
A. Ridley: Music, Value and the Passions (Ithaca, NY, 1995)
R. Scruton: The Aesthetics of Music (Oxford, 1996)